ならず 読んでください

ご指定されたページは存在しません:削除された可能性があります

Sorry !!! The Page which you have accessed had been disappeared or changed.

ポータルサイトにもどる Back to portal page

Deer mandala of the Kasuga Taisha Shrine, fourteenth century Japan. Nara Nationa Museum
Copyleft, CC, Mitzub'ixi Quq Chi'j, 1996-2099
For all undergraduate students!!!
, you do not paste but [re]think my message. Remind Wittgenstein's phrase, "I should not like my writing to spare other people the trouble of thinking. But, if possible, to stimulate someone to thoughts of his own," - Ludwig Wittgenstein
Africa;n Sysu:emfoJf Thought General Editors Charles S. Bird !van Karp Contributing Editors Thomas 0. Beiddman James Fernandez Luc de Heusch John Middleton Roy Willis Gnosis, Philosophy, and the Order of Knowledge MUDil\ifBE lNDlANA UNJVERSJTY PRESS and JAlv!ES CURREY London 0004230142 © 1988 by V. Y. Mudimbe . AH rights reserv~d No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval sys:i:em, without permission in writing from the publisher. The Association of American University Presses' Resolution on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition. Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Catafoging-in-PubHcation Data Mudimbe, V. Y., 1941- The invention of Africa. (African systems of thought) Bibliography: p. Includes index, I. Philosophy, African, 2o Knowledge, Theory of. L Title. IL Series. B5310.M8ti 1988 199'.6 87-45324 ISBN 0-253-33126-9 ISB:N 0-25 3-20468-2. (pbk.) 2 3 4 5 6 94 93 92 91 90 British Library Cataloguing in Pub1icatiol!1 Data Mudimbe, 'V. Y., 1941- The invention of Africa : gnosis, philosophy, and the order of knowledge. - (African systems of thought). L African philosophy L Title H. Series 199'.6 ISBN 0-35255-203-.J (paper) To the memory of James S. Coleman Mors ipsa beatior inde est, quod per cruciamina leti via panditur ardua iustis, et ad astra doloribus itur. -Prudentius, Hymnus Circa Exequias Defuncti CONTENTS INTRODUCTION I. Discourse of Power and Knowledge of Otherness II. Questions of Method III. The Power of Speech IV. E. W. Blyden's Legacy and Questions V. The Patience of Philosophy Conclusion: The Geography of a Discourse APPENDIX. ETHIOPIAN SOURCES OF KNOWLEDGE BIBLIOGRAPHY INDEX ix I 201 205 233 INTRODUCTION This book evolved accidentally; as a result of an invitation to prepare a survey of African philosophy. Strictly speaking, the notion of African philosophy refers to contributions of Africans practicing philosophy within the defined framework of the discipline and its historical tradition (Horton, 1976; Hountondji, 1977). h is only metaphorically, or, at best, from a historicist perspective, that one wnuld extend the notion of philosophy to AJrican traditional systems of thought, considering then1. as dynamic processes in which concrete experiences are integrated into an order of concepts and discourses (Ladri,ere, 1979:14-15). I have thus preferred to speak of African gnosis. J. Fabi,rn used the notion of gnosis in his analysis of a charismatic movement ( r 969 ), In this book, the wider frame seems better suited to the range of problems addressed, aH of which are based on a preliminary question: to what extent can one speak of an African knowledge, and in what sense? Etymologically, gnosis is related to gnosko, which in the acricient Greek means "to know." Specifically, gnosis means seeking to know, inquiry, n:1ethods of knowing, investigation, and even acquaintance with someone, Often the word is used im a more specialized sense, that of higher and esoteric knowledge, and thus it refers to a structured, common, and conventional knowledge, but one strictly under the control of specific procedures for its use as well as transmission. Gnosis is, consequently, different from doxa or opinion, and, on the other hand, cannot be confused with episteme, understood as both science and general intellectual configuration. The title is thus a methodological tool: it embraces the question of what is and what is not African philosophy and also orients the debate in another direction by focusing on conditions of possibility of philosophy as part of the larger body of knowledge on Africa called "Africanism." I use this central notion of conditions of possibility in accordance with a recent tradition in which Michel Foucault could, for example, define his own intellectual ambition in terms of its dependence on alterations that Jean Hyppolite introduced into Hegelian philosophy (Foucault, 1982:235-37). What the notion of conditions of possibilii:y indicates is that discourses have not only sociohistorical origins but also epistemological contexts. h is the latter which make them possible and which can also account for them in an essential way, I shall be dealing with discourses on African societies, cultures, and peoples as signs of something else, li v.~ould like to interrogate their modalities, significance, or strntegies as a means of understanding the type of knowledge which is being proposed. 1n fact, I do not address the classical issues of African anthropology or history, the results of which might or might 1X X Introduction not mirror an objective .African reality. Rather I am looking upstream of the results, precisely at vvhat makes them possible, before accepting them as commentary on revelation, or restitution, of an African experience, The book attempts, therefore, a sort of archaeology of A.frican gnosis as a system of know·ledge in which major philosophical questions recently have arisen: first, concerning the form, the content, and the style of "Africanizing" knowkdge; second, concerning the status of traditional systems of thought and their possible rdation to the normative genre of kno-wledge. From the first chapters, which interrogate W/estern images of Africa, through the chapters analyzin.g the power of anthropologists, missionaries, and ideologists, to the last, on philosophy, I am directly concerned with the processes or transformation of t"ypes or knmNledge, This orientation has two cons,:::quences: on the one hand, an apparent attenuation of the originality of Africzx1 contributions and, on the other, an overemphasis upon external procedures, such as anthropological or religious influences, The fact of the matter is that, until novv, 1Western interpreters as well as African analysts have been using categories and conceptual systems which depend on a Western epistemological order. Evea in the most explicitly "Afrocentric" descriptions, models of analysis explicitly or implicitly, knovvingly or unknowingly, refer to the same order. Does this mean that A..frican Weltanschauungen and African traditional systems of thought are unthinkable and cannot be made explicit within the framework of their own rationality? My ow:1 daim is that thus far the ways in w-hich they have been evaluated and the means used to explain them relate to theories and methods whose constrain:s, mles, and systems of operation suppose a n::m-African episternological iocus. From this viewpoint the claim of some African philosophers such as 0, Bimwenyi (198ra) and E Eboussi-.Boulaga (1981) that they represent an epistemological hiai:us should be taken seriously. What does this mean for the field of African studies? To what extent can their perspectives ~11odify the fact of a silent dependence on a ·\Western episteme? Would it then be possible to n:new the 11otion of tradition from, let es say, a r.adical dispersion of African cultures? These are the most important issues in the debate on African philosophy, They oblige 1ne to clarify imrnediately my positien about represen~atives of African gnosis. Who i.s speaking about it? 1J;!ho has the right and the credentials to produce it, describe it, comment upon it, or ar least present opinions about it? No one takes offonse if an anthropologist is quesi:ioned, But strangely enough, Africanists-and among them anthropologists-have decided to separate the "real" African from the westernized African and to rel.y strictly upon. the first. Rejecting this myth of the "m2.n in ch.e bush," }c Jahn chose to "turn to those Africans vvho h,we their own opinion and who will determine the future of Africa: those, in other words, of vvhom h is said that they are trying to revive the African tradition" (Jahn, 1961:16). Yet, Jahn's decision seems exaggerated. l would prefer a wider authority: intellectuals' discourses as a critical library and, if I could, the experience of rejected Introduction xi forms of wisdom which are not part of the structures of political power and scientific knowledge. In sum, rather than simply accept the authority of qualified representatives of African cultures, I would like to study the theme of the foundations of discourse about Africa. It is obvious that in such a subjective work I cannot claim to offer an exhaustive report analyzing all present tendencies or encompassing all within its frame. This book is only a critical synthesis of the complex questions about knowledge and power in and on Africa. The presuppositions and hypotheses outlined above indicate a range of theoretical alternatives that I have been working on for the last fifteen years. It from L'Autre face du royaume (1973) to L'Odeur du pere (19826) and this contribution, my general view has somewhat changed, I believe that my major thesis has remained the same with respect to the analogical form of the social sciences and the history of Africanist discourse. These disciplines do not provide a real comprehension of the Weltanschauungen studied. Yet one can also say that it is in these very discourses that African .worlds have been established as realities for knowledge. And today Africans themselves read, challenge, rewrite these discourses as a way of explicating and defining their culture, history, and being. It is obvious that since its inception Africanism has been producing its own motives as well as its objects, and fundamentally commenting upon its own being, while systematically promoting a gnosis. From this gnosis ultimately arose both African discourses on otherness and ideologies of alterity of which negritude, black personality, and African philosophy might be considered to be the best established in the present-day intellectual history of Africa. Some of my critics (e.g., Mpoyi-Bwatu, 1983; N'Zembele, 1983; Willame, 1976) have aggressively urged me to draw political implications from my conclusions. Others, such as Mouralis (1981, 1984a), have instead thought my project, that of dealing with taboo themes, overly ambitious. I only hope that some people would agree that the task of bringing philosophy to some of its own limits and metaphors in social science, and that of questioning philosophy's ambiguous contacts with unphilosophical discourses, justify my commitment not to philosophy, nor to an invented Africa, but to what it essentially means to be an African and a philosopher today. I am grateful to L. Kaumba whose phenomenological study of the significance of identity in my literary work (Kaumba, 1986) forced me to reevaluate the implications of my theses about the Same and the Other in philosophical anthropology. Yet his critique meets my fundamental beliefs: identity and alterity are always given to others, assumed by an I- or a We-subject, structured in multiple individual histories, and, at any rate, expressed or silenced according to personal desires vis-a-vis an episteme. This also implies that from a methodological viewpoint I think, as Foucault put it, that "discourse in general and scientific discourse in particular, is so complex a reality that we not only can but should approach it at different levels and with different methods" (1973: xiv). For this essay I have xn Introduction chosen an archaeological perspective that allows me to address the issue of the progressive constitution of an African order of knowledge. However, for reasons having to do with the bizan-e nature of some of the sources usedmainly the anthropological ones-I have preferred not to distinguish the epistemological level of knowledge from the archaeological levd of knowledge, I am deeply indebted to the Joint Committee on African Studies of the Social Science Research Council i.n conjunction with the American Council of Learned Societies. They invited me to write this study and gave me the necessary facilities. A briefer and slightly different form of chapters three and five was published by the African Studies Review in I 9 8 5. The bibliography at the end reveals rny intellectual debt to many works and scholars. Kn this bibliography li present books I have indeed used. I did not think it important to include such authors as Aristotle, Descartes, Diderot, Rousseau, or Voltaire to \IVhom I sometimes refer, in the same manner, it did not seem useful to include a number of narratives and texts by explorers, colonial theorists, and popes. They generally express a normative doxa and its submission to an episteme. As such, they reveal the development of anthropological and philosophical theories, As to non-English books I quote, ]. have often-but not always-consulted the originals, even when the existing translations were excellent" Yet apart from stated exceptions, I generally make reference to English versions when available, H an English edition is not mentioned in the bibliography, the translation is my own. I must express explicidy my gratitude to some friends and colleagues without whom this book would, perhaps, not have been vvritten, or certainly not yet finished: Elizabeth Boyi for her encouragement; Christie Agav,u for her editorial ,Issistance; Kofi Agawu, Paul Riesman, and Ivan Karp for their critical evaluations. I am particularly grateful to Arnd lBohrn, Walter Michener, David I'\Jewbury, and IV!ildred Mortimer, whose patient reading of the entire manuscript and critical comments hdped me darify many points and translate my Gallic style into the English language. li extend my gratitude to Haverford College and in particular to Robert Stevens, Robert Gavin, Jr., Wyatt JVfacGaffeya, nd Judy Young for their support and generosity. Finally I have to express my special thanks to Shirley Averill for her useful suggestions, the typing of many drafts of the manuscript, and her unfailing· patience. Roberta L. Diehl and Janet Rabinowitch, my editors, deserve grateful acknowledgment for their advice, support, and efficiency, Needless to say, the ideas, hypotheses, and interpretations put forth in this book are completely my responsibility. THE INVENTION OF AFRICA J DISC()tJR.SE i,~i,~C-)\1VI~EG,DE OF P()\\;VER.,,.A J\TD L1r) ,:f. () , 1T, .1LH -. -EC,UJr.\.1'1 . ~'~ ---,-£CS 1 d . Co~orni:dng Stn,cture and Marginality Lord have pity on usl ... "The human race?" Phyllis exclaimed, stressing the second word in her astonishment. "That's what it says here," Jinn assured her. "Don't start off by interrupting me." P. BomLE, Planet of the Apes. The scrarn1ble for .Africa, and the most active period of colonization, lasted less than a century. These events, which involved the greater part of the African contin,ent, occurred between the !late nineteenth and the mid-twentieth centuries. Although ln African history the colonial experience repm· sous but a brief n1oment from the perspective of today, this moment is still charged and controversial, s.ince, to say the least, it signified a new historical form and the possibility of radically new types of discourses on African traditions :md cultures. One might think that this new historical form has meant, from its origins, the negation of rwo contradictory myths; namely, the "Hobbesian picture of a pre-European Africa, in which there was no account of Tin1e; no Arts; no Letters; no Society; and vvhich is worst of aH, continu,ed fear, and danger of violent death''; and "the Rousseaui.an picture of an African golden age of perfect liberi:y; equalhy and fraternity" (Hodgkin, 19 57: 174-75 ). Although generalizations are of course dangerous, colonialism and colonization basically mean organization, arrangement. The two words derive from the latin vvard colere, meaning to cultivate or to design, Indeed the historical colonial experience does not and obviously cannot reflect the peaceful connotations of these words. But it can be admitted that the colonists (those settling a. region), as well as the colonialists (those exploiting a territort by dominating a local majority) have all tended to organize and transform non-European areas into fundamentally European constructs. I 2 The Invention of Africa 1 -...,vouldsu ggest that in looking at this process, it is possible ro use rhree main keys to account for the modulations and methods representative of colonial organization: the procedures of acquiring, distributing, and exploiting lands in colonies; the policies of domesticating natives; and the manner of managing ancient organizations and implementing new modes of prcducfion. Thus, three complementary hypotheses and actions emerge: the domination of physical space, th~ reformation of natives' minds, and the integration of local economic histories into the 'Western perspective. These complementary projects constitute what might be caUed the colonizing structure, vvhich completely embraces the physical, human, and spiritual aspects of the colonizing experience (see, e.g., Christopher, 1984: 27-87). This structure dearly also indicates the projected me,:amorphosis envisioned, at great intellectual cost, by ideological and theoretical texts, which from the last quarter of the nineteenth century to the 1950s have proposed programs for "regenerating" the African space and its inhabitants. A. Cesaire thinks that the great historical trngedy of Africa has been not so much that it ',vas too late in making contact with the rest of the world, as the manner in which that contact vvas brought about; that Europe began to propagate at a time when it had fallen into the hands of the most unscrupulous financiers and captains of industry. (Cesaire, 1972:2.3) He refers to the second part of the nineteenth century, emphasizing the coexistence of "imperialist" ideology, economic and political processes for extending control over African space, and capitalist institutions which uJtimately led to dependence and underdevelopment (see also Mazrui, 197 4). In a recent book, D. K Fieldhouse writes that "only a dogrnatist would attempt to stat,e categorically that colonialiGm was either totally inc::msistent Vlith economic development in the dependencies or, alternatively, that i.t was the best possible medium for stimulating their growth. Colonialism was not sufficiently consistent over time to justify any such sweeping assertions, nor were its objeccives sufficiently coherent to achieve ,my particular result" (1981:103). Thus colonialism has been some kind of historical accident, a "largely unplanned and, as it turned out, transient phase in the evolving relationship between more and less deVeloped parts of the vvorld" (1981:49). This accident, on the whole, according to this view, was not the worst thing that could have happened to the black continent. Essentially, the argument is not new. It has a history that goes back to the debate of the early decades of this century. In his book, Imperialism: A Study, J. A. Hobson linked the scramble for Africa to capitalism and capitalist search for higher profits from coionial conquests. For J, A. Schumpei: er, in 1919, colonialism as well as its cause, imperialism, did not obey logic. It was "non-rational and irrational purely instinctual inclinations tovvard war and conquest" that guided "objectless tendencies toward forcible Powe;" and Otherness 3 expansion, without definite, utilitarian limits" (Schum peter, I 9 5 I: 8 3 ). Against the Leninist theme of Imperialism, the Highest Stage of Capitalism (1917), he stated that "a purely capitalist world offers no fertile soil to hnperiaHst impulses ... capitalism is by nature anti-imperialist" (1951:96), And i.n a voluminous document full of statistics, The Balance Sheets of Imperialism ( I 9 3 6), Grover Clark demonstrated that colonialism was not only economicaHy irrational but also ruinous for the colonial powers, On the opposite side, at i:he risk of being labeled dogmatists, !v1arxist interpreters accept the essentials of Lenin's thesis. The contention of neol ½arxists such ;;s Samir Amin, Paul Baran, Andre Gunder-Frank, and Immarmd ·1~'Vallerstein is that if colonialism vvas inconsistent with economic development, it was at least, since its inception, quite consistent with its ovvn economic interests and objectives. Accordingly, colonialism should have produced a body of knowledge on the means of exploiting dependencies (Rodney, 1981). h should also have produced a kind of empirical technique for implementing structural distortions by positing fom main political propositions: first, priority given to the industrial revolution over the agricultural revolution; second, the simultaneous promotion of all branches of indusuy with a preferential approach to heavy industry; third, emphasis 011 tertiary and service activities; fourth, preference for exports to the detriment of the total economic system (Amin, 1973). The outcome of these policies was the process of underdevelopment initiated everywhere colonialism occurred. This process can be summed up in t~'lree points: First, the capitalist world system is such that parts of the system alvvays devdop at the expense of other parts, either by trade or by the transfer of surpiuses, Second, the uJt1derdevelopment of dependencies is not only an absence of development, but also an organizational structure created under colonialism by bringing non- '\;i/estern territory into the capitalist world. Third, despite 'cheir economic potential, dependencies lack the structural capacity for autonomy and sustained grovvth, since their economic fate is fargely determined by the developed countries (Arnin, 1974; Gunder-Frank, 1969; 1X1aHerstein, 1979). From this last contention, some theorists have quickly hypothesized that if Japan has escaped the predicament of under .. development, it is because it is the only non- 'iJf/estern country to have escaped colonialism (Bigo, 1974:32, 60). It seems impossible to make any statement about colonialism withom being a dogmatist, particular! y ,Nhere economic organization and growth are concerned. Different as they are in form and intention, the Ivfa,rxist z,nd peripher,d theories have nevertheless the same focus: overseas territory, totally reorganized and submitted to a \Jvestern model (Mommsen, 19 8 3 ). The first theory considers colonial imperialism as a calculated and inevitable culffJination of capitalism. If the fatter discounts the planned aspect of colonialism, it still assumfcs the phenomenon to be a consequence of European industrializatian and development, somehow· bound to expand overseas. 'v;"lhateverth eory one accepts, the application remains the same, leading 4 The Invention of Africa inevitably ::o what I have called the coionizing structure responsible for producing m2,rgi.aal societies, cuhcures, and human beings (~~mmanuel, 1969; Bairoch, 1971). Therefore, for the purpose of darity further on, let me make dear the dichotomy that this stmcture creates and ,.vhich is a sign ol ,1vhat L Sachs c:?.lls "euroi:;eocentrism." It is a model which dominates our thought and given irn projection on the -world scale by the expansion of capitalism and the colonial phenomeno,1, it marks contemporary cuh2re imposing itself as 8. strongly conditioning model foe some and forced d"cu!turatioa for others. (Sachs, 1971:22; quoted by Bigo, 1974:23, n.3) Because of the colonializing structure, a dichotomizing system has emerged, and 1.vith it ;;, great number of current paradigmatic oppositions have developed: traditional versus modern; oral versus written and printed; agrafian and customary conmmnities -,ersus urban and industrialized civilization; subsistence economies versus highly productive economies. In Africa a gr.eat deal of attention is generaUy given to the evolution implied and promised by the passage frona the former paradigms to the latter (Iv'iudimbe, 1980). This presupposed jump frmn one extremity (underdevelopment) to the other (devdopment) is in fact misleading. By emphasizing the formulation oli 1techniques of economic change, the model tends to neglect a structural mode inherited from ,colonialism, Between the t'wo extremes there is an intennediat::, 2. diffosed sp.1ce in -which social and econornic events define 1:he extent of marginality (Bigo, 1974::w; Shaw, 1985:?,3-36). At 1:he economi.c level, for examplf::, if the relatively ]m,v producfrvity of traditional proces,es of praductioa (formerly adapted to the then-existing mzrkets and range of trade and exchanges) has been dismpted by a new division of labor which depends upon international markets, then transformation has meant 2. progressive destruction of traditional realms of agriculture and crafts (t,/[eillassoux, 1975:u5)a As a second examp!ie, one could reg21rd the social disintegration of African societies and the growing urban proletariat as results of a destabilization of customary organizations by an incoherent establishment of new social arrangemtnts and institutions (Turnbull, 1962; Memmi, 1966; I\fair, 1975). Finally, if at the cultural and religious levels, through schools, churches, press, and audio-visual media the colonializing enterprise diffused new attitudes which were contradictonJ and richly complex models in tt~rms of culture, spiritual values, and their transmission, it also broke the rnltur2Jly unified and rehgiously integrated schema of most African tr:0-ditions (Bimwenyi, 198ra), From that rnomeni: on the forms and fornmiations of the colonial culture and its aims were somehow the means of trivializing the 'Whole traditional n:mde of lifo and its spiritual frannework. The polfenti?1l and necessary transformations meant that the mere presence of this new culture 'Nas a reasor1 for the rejection of unadapted persons and confused minds. Power and Otherness 5 Marginality designates the intermediate space bet"/, or from the genesis of this finality itseH. Thus, according to Ebou:ssi-Boulaga, the recit is a reconsrrucdon cf history. By necessity a negation of the present, and also a negation 0£ sdf, it is, at the same time, the only critical way to self. hs internal dynamism will, eventually, guarantee the reconciliation of the htstorical reason and a reasonable freedom for the Muntu. The historical reason and reasonable liberti; are rested from experienced 1-nadness and arbitrariness. They zxe the inversion and reversal of madness and arbitrariness. The discourse v,hich is being constituted by the being for-itself should describe in a concrete way the future of the for-itself in history, in a regional history, whose reach is universal because of the being of the subject, the subject of history. (Eboussi-Boulaga, 1977:223) The notion of critical reading, as vvell as that of a riicit pour soi that might produce a regional historical account of the global history of humankind, bring us back to Levi-Strauss's and Foucault's annihiiation of the mythologies of the Same. from this perspective, R l'vfoore's classical mies on scientific strategies and their metaphors-e.g., "in science, as in art, we are compelled to make estimates about promising and unpromising lines of attack" (19 5 8)-seem dreams of a questionable conjunction of science, knowledge, and power. Levi-Strauss insists: 'Who is speaking about science? Do we know hov1 to live ·with others? "The formula 'hell is other people,' which has achieved such vvidespread fame, is not so much a philosophical proposition as an ethnographical statement about ['~Vestern] civilization. For, since childhood, we have been accustomed to fear impurity as coming from without. When they assert, on the contrary that 'hell is ourselves,' savage peoples give us a lesson in humility which, it is to be hoped, vve may still be capz.ble of understanding" (Levi-Strauss, 1979:507). This ethical lesson stems from an anthropological context. Eboussi-Boufaga's discourse deploys itself in rhe order of an amplification conceived from an African perspective. Foucault, in the conclusion of his survey of the history of insanity in the Age of Reason, notes that "Nietzsche's last cry, proclaiming himself both Christ and Dionysos, is not on the border of reason and unreascn, ... but the point where [art] becomes impossible and where it n1ust fall silent" (1965:287). l think a number of African thinkers would identify with Nietzsche's claim, in a figurative way. The amplification is obvious. fa it pure accident that a great number of leading African intellectuals have, between I 9 5 5 and 1970, worked strenuously publishing works on some really "compromising" European Questions of Method 43 thinkers? To note just a few: Elungu specialized in Nlalebranche's philosophy; Hountondji chose Husserl and Comte; Senghor commented upon Teilhard de Charclin's theses; Towa was then working on Hegel, Ngindu beginning his book on Laberthonniere, and Ugirashebuja completing his research on Heidegger. In these enterprises one notes a remarkable media,· tion between the rigor of a phik,sophica1 exercise and the fantasies of a political insurrection: the text commented upon is a mirror which reveals the self to the reader or commentator. From an idealist epistemology come questions and propositions which, on the one hand, seem dose to Sartre's political aesthetics for the liberation of the Third World and, Ofi the other, transpose into African geography Foucault's and Levi-Strauss's critiques of such notions as history, culture, human space, and conventions. This clear amplification is sufficient reason for me to state that despite their violence against the rule of the Same and the history of its conquests over all regionalisms, specificities, and differences, Levi-Strauss and l'bucault, as well as a number of African thinkers, belong to the signs of the same power, W,nat the11 represent could be considered an expression of the "intelligence" of the Same. As Foucault himself stated, referring to his own intellectual filiation: "Cam one still philosophize where Hegel i.s no longer possible? Can any philosophy continue to exist that is no longer Hegelian?" And more precisely: "truly to escape Hegel involves an exact appreciation of the price vve have to pay to detach ourselves from him. It assumes that we are mvare of the extent to which Hegd, insidiously perhaps, is dose to us; it implies a knowledge in that which permits us to think against Hegel, of that which rem.aims Hegelian" (1982:235). One could also relate Levi-Strauss's view to this same origin, or, more convincingly, to Kant's dream about metaphysics and anthropology (see Levi-Strauss, 1968). The apparent profanation represented by these projects might simply be an optical iHusion, Levi-Strauss and Foucault are engulfed in the history of the Same and its contradictions. l would not say that African irnteHectuals are engulfed in the same vvay. The passion that in Levi-Strauss's and Foucault's works presents theories about norm, rule, and system only uncovers and seeks strictly to define this complex history of an identity~ In the name of the same methodological principles, Africans tend-despite differences of fanguage and education-to doubt the ethical value of these estimations (see e,g., Hountondji, I977; Wiredu, 1980), Seen from the frontiers of the 'flestem power-knowledge system, all these choices seem stimulating, Still, one can meditate on their projects as possible symbols of a failed will to transcendence, now expressing its desire towards an ambiguous new beginning, However, it is important to note that African ideology, as a body of reflexions and questions, springs from the same lines of dissolution that, in the kingdom of the Same, allowed Levi-Strauss's and Foucault's crises. Metaphorically speaking, in Nietzsche's confusion there is not only the silence of an art and a power-knowledge, but also, insistently, there are all the promises of Kant's old question on the possibility of an anthropology: how pertinent is it to speak about humans? I1f,] rfHE PO'\X7E1Ol F SPl~ECI-I The EviissfoiJlary'sD iscourse mnd Africa's GDnversion In fact, I am novv so accustomed to the paradoxes of this planet that I wrote the preceding sentence without thinking of the absurdity it represents. P. BouLLE, Planet of the Jtpes. It takes little imagination to realize that missionary discourses on Africans were powerful. They were both signs and symbols of a cultural modeL For quite a long time, along with travelers' accounts and anthropologists' interpretations, they constituted a ki.nd of knowledge. In the first quarter of this century, it was dear that the travder had. become a colonizer and the anthropologist, his scientific advisor, while the missionary, more vigorously than ever, continued, in them-y as well as in practice, to expound the model of African spiritual and cultural metamorphosis. The missionary's particular position in the process of Africa's conversion has led to very peculiar results (Bureau, 1962:248-62). These results, intersecting with ideological perspectives, have, on the one hand, fostered African theories of otherness and, on the other, brought about serious doubt concerning the pertinence of Western discourses on African societies. Thus, we have two magnifio~nt actors: the missionary and his African successor, both of them presenting their views on policies of conversion, basing thert'l on what African culture is supposed to be, and utilizing anthropology as a means of dominating or liberating African people (Hastings, r97rII9-2o)o The theme to investigate is the articulation betwr:'.en missionary language and its African echo or negation, and the ultimate consequences of this relationship for anthropology. The investigation is appropriate in view of questionable hypotheses about missionaries' positive or negative contributions to African ideology, and, in general, of the controversial interpretations of this relationship in the crisis of African Studies. For the sake of clarity, I shall address first the subject of missionary discourse; second, the African response; third, how they mingle historically and ideologically in an anthropological locus and have ad valorern responsibility in the building of an African ideology of otherness. 44 The Power of Speech 45 The more carefully one studies the history of missions in Africa, the more difficult it becomes not to identify it with cultural propaganda, patriotic motivations, and cmnmercial interests, since the missions' program is indeed more complex than the simple transmission of the Christian faith. From the sixteenth century to the eighteenth, missionaries were, through aH the "new worlds," part of the political process of creating and extending the right of European sovereignty over "newly discovered" lands (Keller, Lissitzyn, and Mann, 1938). In doing so, they obeyed the "sacred instructions" of Pope Alexander VI in his bull Inter Caetera (1493): to overthrO\V paganism and establish the Christian faith in all barbarous nations. The bulls of Nicholas V-Dum Diversas (q.52) and Romanus Pontifex (1455)-had indeed already given the kings of Portugal the right to dispossess and eternally enslave Mahometans, pagans, and black peoples in general (Deschamps, 1971). Dum Diversas dearly stipulates this right to invade, conquer, expell, and fight (invadendi, conquirendi, expugnandi, clebellandi) Muslims, pagans, and other enemies of Christ (saracenos ac paganos, aliosque Christi inimicos) wherever they may be. Christian kings, following the Pope's decisions, could occupy pagan kingdoms, principalities, lordships, possessions (regna, principatus, Dominia, possessiones) and dispossess them of their personal properry, lane\, and whatever they might have (et mobilia et immobilia bona quaecurnque per eos detenta ac possessa). The king and his successors have the power and right to put these peoples into perpetual slavery (subjugandi illorumque personas in perpetuam servitutem). (See Bimwenyi, r98rn:621•- 22). The missionaries, preceding or foHowing a European flag, not only helped thei.r home country to acquire new lands but also accomplished a "divine" mission ordered. by the Holy Father, Dominator Dominus. It was in God's name that the Pope considered the planet his franchise and established the basic principles of terra nullius (nobody's land), which denies non-Christian natives the right to an autonomous political existence and the right to own or to transfer ownership (Witte, 19 5 8). H the Reformation challenged the Holy Father's power "to give, grant and assign forever" lands to European monarchs, the new axiom, cuius regio, illius religio, enforced the complementariry between colonial activity and religious conversion, For instance, the Christian kingdom of Congo, was officially recognized by the Holy See and the major European seapowers in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. However, it lost its special status in the mercantilist and Protestant eighteenth century. The prevalent economic ideal of a "balance of trade" was inseparable from the need to increase the nation's wealth and its strength, hence the great utility of colonial trade and possess10ns, The Church's involvement in establishing Western sovereign'CIw/ as important both before and after the Reformation, The mass celebrated on the Guinea Coast in I 4 8 I, under a big tree displaying the royal arms of Portugal, symbolized the possession of a new territory. Among a multitude of other similar acts, Vasco Da Gama erected a pillar, engraved with the Portuguese The Invention of Africa royal arms, on the easit coast in the kingdom of Melinda, and Diego Caon constmcted another in 149~. at the mouth of the Congo River. These symbols v,ere part of a formal and elaborate cerernony of appropriation of a term nullius. Generally, such a ceremony presented three major characteristics (Keller et aL, 1938): (a) the constn.mtion of a physical sign bearing the royal arms, such as a pillar (Portuguese), a landmark or even a simple pile of stones (Spanish), or a cross (English and French); (b) a solemn declaration, perhaps presenting the letters patent received from the king, announcing the new srnrereignty and indicating that the possession is taken in the name of, or for, th,~ king; and (c) a symbolization of the new jurisdiction. Explorers from Roman Catholic nations, generally, performed a mass; whereas Anglo-Saxons symbolized their control over the land with a sacred formula or legal decree. For example, on August 5, 1583, as part of the ceremony of taking possession of Newfoundland, Sir Humphrey Gilbert promulgated a code of three laws; namely, the establishment of the Chmch of England in the colony; the punishment as high treason of any act prejudicial to the Queen's right of possessing the necw land; and, for "those uttering words to the Queen's dishonour, the penalty to be having their ears removed and their ship and goods confiscated" (see, e.g., Keller et al., 1938). The missionary played an essential role in the general process of ex;;,ropriation and, subsequently, exploitation of aH the "new found lands" upon the earth. As G. Williams puts it, if in many areas his presence "helped t~ soften the harshness of European impact on the indigenous peoples w110se lands were invaded and exploited," hif "fervour v,ras allied, rather than opposed to commercial motive" (Williams, 1967:2.9). The scramble for Africa in the nineteenth century took place in an atmosphere of Christian revival: the age of Enllghtenment and its critidsm of religion had ended. Coleridge's phrase, "the Bible finds you," was an apt one for all Christians. In Catholic Europe, the First Vatican Council firmly reorganized Catholicism, A group of distinguished prelates even reevaluated the meaning of the so-called curse of Ham, hoping that "the interior of Africa may participate in the solemn con1ing joy of the Church's triumph" (Interior Africa solemnis gaudii proximi Ecde.siae triumphi particeps fiat) (Bimwenyi, 1981:625-26). There was, besides, a general spirit of adventure in the air (Rotberg, 1970; Betts, 1975). The European political and economic rivalries were an incentive to action overseas. The success of men like Cecil Rhodes reinforced the myth of an African treasure hm:se and appeaied to young and ambitious potential colonists. Above all, scientific curiosity and philamhropic objectives combined and confused the struggle against the slav-e trade, geographic explorations, and mythologies about "poor savage Africans" (H2mmond and Jablow, 1977). Three major figures, from the fifteenth century to the end of the nineteenth, determined modalities and the pace of maste:ring, colonizing, and transforming the "Dark Continent": the explorer, the soldier, and the missionary (Christopher, 1984). The explorer, at the end oithc fifteenth century, The Power of Speech 47 was looking for a sea-route to India. Later on, he concerned himself with mapping out the cominent and, in the nineteenth centu.ry, compiling information and organizing complex bodies of knowledge, including medicine, geography, and anthropology. The soldier constituted the most visible figure of the expansion of European jurisdiction" He built castles and forts on the coasts, was in charge of trading posts, participated in the slave-trade, and, in rhe nineteenth century, implemented colonial power" Finally, there was the missionary, whose objective has been, throughout the centuries, the most consistent: to expand "the absoluteness of Christianity" and its virtues. Of aH "these bearers of the African burden," the missionary was also, paradoxicaHy, the best symbol of the colonial enterprise (see Kalu, 1977)" He devoted himself sincerdy to the ideals of colonialism: the expansion of Civilization, the dissemination of Christianity, and the advance of Progress. Pringle's 1820 vision sums it up nicely: Let us enter upon a new and nobler career of conquest. Let us subdue Savage Africa by justice, by kindness, by the talisman of Christian truth. Let us thus go forth, in the name and under the blessing of Goel, gradually to e-.A:tentdh e moral influence ... the territorial boundary also of our colony, until it shall become an Empire" (Hammond and Jablow, 1977:44) Obviously, the missionary's objectives had to be co-extensive with his country's political and cultural perspectives on colonization, as vvell as with the Christian view of his mission" '¾.X/itehq ual enthusiasm, he served as an agent of a political empire, a representative of a civilization, and an envoy of God" There is no essential contradiction betvveen these roles. AH of them implied the same purpose: the conversion of African minds and space. A. J" Christopher rightly observes that "missionaries, possibly more than members of other branches of the colonial establishment, aimed at the radical transformation of indigenous society . " , They therefore sought, whether consciously or unconsciously, the desuuction of pre-colonial societies and their replacement by new Christian societies in the image of Europe" (1984:83)0 One might consider that missionary speech is always predetermined, preregulated, let us say colonized. It depends upon a normative discourse already given, definitely fixed, dearly meant in "a vital connection between Christianity and Western culture as a whole" (Dickson, 1984:33). Missionary orthodox speech, even when imaginative or fanciful, evolved within the framework of what, from now on, I shall call the authority of the truth. Thi.s is God's desire for the conversinn of the world in terms of cultural and sociopolitical regeneration, economic progress and spiritual salvation" This means, at least, that the missionary does not enter into dialogue with pagans and "savages" but must impose the law of God that he incarnates, AH of the non-Christian cultures have to undergo a process of reduction to, or-in missionary language-01 regeneration in, the norms that the missionary The fovention of Africa represents. This undertaking is perfectly logical: a person whose ideas and mission come from and are sustained by God is rightly entitled to the use of all possible means, even violence, to achieve his objectives. Consequently, "African conversion," rather than being a positive outcome of a dialogueunthinkable per se--,came to be the sole position i:he African could take in order to s:urvive as a human being. lin dealing v1ith this kind of general theory, we need models to refer to. I propose to use three men: the seventeenth-century Italian Giovanni Francesco Romano; the nineteenth-century African Samuel Ajayi. Crowi:her; and the twentieth-century Belgian Placide Frans Tempels. These individuals were neither the best of all missionaries, nor necessarily the most remarkable. Yet one easily recognizes that each one, in his time, was an excellent example of sound commitment to religious interests and imperial policy. Giovanni E Romano, a missionar1 in the Congo from 1645 to 1654, published in 1648 a report of fewer than one hundred pages on his voyage to, and his sojourn in, that central African kingdom (Romano, 1648). He really presents no reasons for supposing that the Congolese cannot understand the Gospel's message. His conception of mission coincides with traditional practice. It struck me that, as a missionary, he could have accomplished the same t-Jpe of work with St. Boniface in Germany. He boasts of the number of people converted, masses celebrated, sacraments given, churches erected, but he cannot stand the presence of Dutch Protestants, those "enemies of the Catholic faith," nemici delta Santa Fede Cattolica, who undermine the impression of European grandeur and unity, Romano defines his own mission as working "God's field" la Vigna del Signore, and "preaching God's news" predicare la parola di Dia, to the "poor and pagan" Congolese, questi gentili, quei poveri, etc. For a soldier of God, this does not e.xdude concern for the privileges of rank and for the continuation of this friendly Christian kingdom of Congo. Romano and his colleagues intervene in the conflict between the Congolese monarch and one 0£ his rebel vassals, since a Christi. an monarch is a treasure that must be preserved at any cost. About the Catholic Congolese monarch Garcia H he wrote: "The devotion that His Majesty has showed for our religion, convent and school is a praiseworthy thing for eternitlj'' (Romano, 1648:37). Romano's language is a language of orthodoxy, the expression of the Holy Faith. Few derogatory words occur in his report. In his ethnographic description of the kingdom, the African customs are neither curious nor bizarre (Mudimbe-Boyi, 1977\ Except for the king and his courtiers, all the inhabitants are poor and pagan people. This is not a paradox. Romano describes an African version of a Christian European kingdom with its dukes, earls and barons. With such a model, it is perfectly normal to observe a rigid hierarchy determined by social status and position or, in terms of the interpretation current in Romano's time, by God's will. The only major difference between the model and its African expression appears in a metaphor of colors-white versus black: "The natives of Congo are all of them The Power of Speech 49 black, some more, some less. At birth, they are not black but white and then gradually they become black" (Mudimbe-Boyi, 1977:375-83). At the heai"t of Romano's conviction lies the desire for the universality of God's law. At the same time he hopes to overcome Satan's presence in the African vigna delta Christianita (field of Christianity) and promote the essenza della verita (essence of truth). The second model is Samuel Ajayi Crowther. Born about 1806, this former slave and native of Yorubaland in Nigeria was educated at Fourah Bay College (Sierra Leone) and in England. Ordained a minister in 1843 within the Church Miss10nary Society, he became in 1864 the first Anglican bishop of "the territories of Western Equatorial Africa beyond the Queen's Dominions." An untiring missionary, he participated in several explorations, among them the voyage that he related in his Journal of an Expedition Up the Tshadda Rivers, published in I 8 5 5. Crowther believed that Africa could regenerate herself without the help of others (Meester, 19806:72; Sanneh, 1983:60-83). However, in presenting his own experience, he tends to refer to contemporary classification of "savages" and from this perspective builds his own project of converting his African brethren to civilization and Christianity. About his r 8 5 4- Niger expedition, for instance, Crowther recalls: I asked whether the inhabitants of Gomkoi were Pagans or Mohammedans; and was informed that they were all Pagans; that the males wore some sort of cloth around their loins, but the females only a fow green leaves. On asking whether they were cannibals, I was answered in the negative. (In Hammond and Jablow, 1977:36) What i.s interesting i.n this brief quotation is its classificatory implications, in particular the characteristics selected: paganism, nakedness, and cannibalism. Western-assimilated, Crowther intends to relate an ethnographic case objectively, but he is very dearly describing the syndrome of savagery. As D. Hammond and A. Jablow rightly put it: The basic attitudes which arbitrarily relate these essentially unrelated qualities-paganism, nakedness, cannibalism-are those which assign all cultural differences to the single category of savagery; and one trait as it distinguishes a savage from a European becomes an index to the existence of the other traits which are part of the syndrome. (Hammond and Jablow, 1977:36-37) In fact, far from making Crowther responsible for this syndrome, I am inclined to look at him as expressing the signs of an episteme. He simply shares a pervasive evoRutionary assumption, a tendency to see in Africans only these indexed features and thus subsequently to indicate the necessity of a regeneration through both a cultural and spiritual conversion (see figure 2). The Invention of Africa Figure 1 •• Ideological 1\fodd of Conversion: Colonial Rufo Premises Status Prl\mitiveness Symbols Pagan (evil) or signs Naked (child) Cannibal (beast) Method Anthropological presuppositions Mediators Aims Conversion Civilization Christianity Christian (good) Education Civilized (adults) Evolution "Evolue" (human being) Missiology, Colonial applied sciences anthropology, pedagogy My third model is the Belgian Placide F. Tempels, a missionary in Central Africa from 1933 to 1962 and author of Bantu Philosophy. Placide Tempds was a very serious and careful student of Bantu culture, despite allegations to the contrary made n-1.ainlyb y professional anthropologists and philosophers, who are inclined to emphasize formal training as the sine qua non condition of sound work Tempels had lived more than ten years among the Luba Katanga people, sharing their language and culture when he decided to publish his experiences (1979:3-25), Rather than as a philosophical treatise, his Bantu Philosophy could be understood simultaneously as an indication of religious insight, the expression of a cultural doubt about the supposed backwardness of Africans, and a political manifesto for a new policy for promoting "civilization" and Christianity, But this complexity is not what is commonly discussed when specialists speak of Tempels's philosophy. It must be remembered that Bantu Philosophy is based on very simple ideas, They go like this. First, in all cultures, life and death determine human behavior; or, presented differently, all human behavior depends upon a system of general principles, Second, if the Bantu are human beings, there is reason to seek the fundamentals of their beliefs and behavior, or thc;ir basic philosophical system. From this position, Ternpds attempts "a tme estimate of i.ndi.genous peoples," rejecting "the misunderstanding and fanaticism of the ethnology of the past and of the former attitude of aversion entertained Twith regard to them" (Possoz's preface in Tempels, 1959:13-15). This meant questioning the classical doctrines about evangelization, civilization and coloniz:1tion (Tempels, I 9 5 9: I 67-8 9 ). These three models-Giovanni Francesco Romano, Samuel Ajayi Crowther, and Placide Frans Tempels--signi.fy the authority of the truth, its signs and discourse, 'vile can perceive in them an expression of a common ideology. They are, all of them, people for whom commitment to God is central. Concretely, they believe that they are the ones in charge of saving The Power of Speech Africa. This, for them, means the promotion of the ideals of Christian civilization. Finally, they are secure in their knowledge of the correct means for Africa's conversion. In brie~ they prove right M. de Certeau's observation that "the credibility of a discourse is what first makes believers act in accord with it. It produces practitioners" (Certeau, 1984:148). In his evaluation of Christianity from an African point of view, EboussiBoulaga, the philosopher from Cameroon, holds that in general missionary discourse has always been presented as a discourse of philosophical reduction and ideological intolerance: Christianity is the inheritor of Greek reason and it is the continuation and the achievement of the Judaic revelation. By these two traits it is the critic of the falsehood of other religions and denounces their mythological character. Its proper element is language and history, but not the obscure regions of the cosmos nor of the imaginary. That is why it agrees with modernity and resists better than other systems the corrosion of modernity, the disillusion of the world in which it exists. (Eboussi-Boulaga, 19 8 r: 3 5) Sharing this belief in the superiority of Christianity, expressed in its essential qualifications, that is, its identification with reason, history, and power, the missionary's discourse has, according to Eboussi-Boulaga, always presented five major features. First of all, it is a language of derision, insofar as it fundamentally ridicules the pagan's Gods. And one must not forget that since its birth Christianity has appropriated for itself both the only way to true communication with the divine and the only correct image of God and God's magnificence. Second, it is a language of refutation or systematic reduction: all pagan religions constitute the black side of a white transcendental Christianity, and this metaphoric opposition of colors means the opposition of evil and good, Satan and God. The third feature illuminates the missionary's pragmatic objectives: his action is supported by a language of demonstration, which reflects God's truth. In order to sustain his derision for and refutation of non-Christian beliefs and practices, the missionary emphasizes the Christian faith in terms of its historical coherence and transforming virtues. Religious and biblical categories enter into the logic of his civilization, thus making sacred a cultural model and giving it a divine seal. Consequently, there is a fourth characteristic: the rule of Christian orthodoxy which relates Faith to knowledge of the only Truth. This is the cornerstone of the belief in the supremacy of the European experience, the support of a fantastic set of principles. It accounts for the following major principles: first, that the Christian characteristic resides in the quality of Faith and not in moral grandeur; second, that it is Faith which promotes and gives sense to ethics and not the contrary. The last trait of missionary discourse relates to these two axioms and their theological significance: it is a language that conforms to these vigorous axioms. Missionary speech and praxis prove that no human enterprise can succeed as long as the true God is not The Invention of Africa acknovvledged. The Christian God's spirit appears, therefore, as history's only force. 1 vvould prefer to simplify this analytical perspective of Eboussi-Boulaga's into a simpler scheme, The missionar1 language of defision is basically a cuhurni posjtion, the expression of an ethnocentric outlook. The aspects of refutadon and demonstration rationalize the initial ethnocentric moment and are aimed explicitly towards an intellectual reduction that v,rould complement the mles of orthodoxy and conformity. Thus we have three moments, rather than types, of violence in missionary language. Theoretically, they are expressed in the concepts of derision, refutation-demonstration, and orthodoxy-conformity. Taking into account the missionary theology of salvation, and more precisely the general policies of conversio gentium, it becomes dear that the same violence is linked to the spiritual and cultural process of-conversion in a hypostatic uni.on (see figure 3). AU missionaries, whatever their denominations, operate according to the same canon of conversion. Their language depends on three major types of data always considered a given and taken for granted: premises, mediators, and objectives. All of them tend to integrate cultural and religious aims, the mission being altogether oriemed towards the culturd promotion and spiritual salvation of "savages." Thus, for instance, C F. Romano's preaching of the Holy Faith to "these needy" also implied involvement in political affairs to perpetuace a 'Western Christian dependent polity iI'. Africa. Bishop Crowther was preoccu.pied with both Christianization and 'JVesternization of "naked, cannibal, and pagan primitives." Tempds stated his philosophy of civihzing Bantu people in this way: "H the Bamu cannot be raised by a Christian civilization, they will not be by any other" (1959:186). The pertinent categories arise from a stru.ctural combination. On the one hand, ethnographic commentaries on African peoples are arranged according to tbe prm;pect of their possible conversion.; on the other hand, specific socio-cultural symbols designate the passage from primitiveness to civilization, An evolutionary thesis expresses the conversion from savagery and Satan's dark1.1ess to the light of civilization and God's kingdom. The transformation is sometimes described as the introduction or restoration of health in a sick universe, the establishment of order in a world of disorder, madness, corruption, and diabolical illusions (see Pirntte, 1973; Fernandez, 1979 ). In its standard form, the process of conversion which is the path tc a "civitlized liie" is presented as a gradual one: at the lowest level one finds primitives or pagans; these, infected by the "will to become \~'esternized" become catechumens; the zenith of their development is achieved when they become Christians or "evolues," that is, V/estemized individuals. Accordingly, the missionary's language presents rhree major approaches: derision of so-called primitive religions and their gods, refutation and demonstration to convince The Power of Speech 53 Figure 3. "fhe Missionary Theology of S;cihration Premises Status Primitiveness Symbols Illness Disorder (madness, satanic iliusions, and corrnption) Darkness Method Derision Mediators Conversion to introduce to restore to establish to promote .Aims Western Civilization and Christianity I-!ea!th Order (Christian models of faith and behavior) The Light of God and Civilization Demonstration Conformity the evolving Africans, and imposition of rules of orthodoxy and conformity for converts. Quite inevitably the Christian faith has for many years ... been inextricably bound up with this Western aggression . .But it has also to be admitted quite frankly that during these cer.turies the missionaries of the Christian Church have commonly assumed that 'iJVestern civilization and Christianity \Vere two aspects of the same gift which they were commissioned to offer to the rest or mankind. This assumption was sometimes quite conscious and was explicitly stated. More often it was quite unconscious and would have been indignantly denied. But in neither case are we called upon to judge our fathers. Their sincerity can hardly be disputed. (Taylor, I 96 3: 5-6) Fundamentally, an evoludonary assumption vvas expressed on the basis of a dualistic anthropology (see J,Jgimbi-Nseka, 1979:10 and 18-19), As Benedict XV put it in his encydic, Mctxir11umI llud (1919), missionaries must be determined to oppose Satan and to bring salvation to the "poor people of Africa victimized by evil forces." -Yei: one notes that Romano focused on mediators and aims rather than on premises. And Tempels absolutely doubted the classical process of conversion: he was not sure in the least that assimilation constituted the best way, and he hated the "(;:volues," whom he considered to be bad copies of Europeans. Moreover, he did not believe that to Christianize meant to impose a "\;;Vesternp hilosophical anthropology (Tempels, 1962). However, Tempels's position did not imply a complete negation of the essential dualism but only indicated another type of guidance for the promotion o.f orthodoxy and conformity. The emphasis he gave to l\antu ontology, for example, means th:u he had faith in the possibility of bringing about a "new Christian civilization" without destroying Bantu values or their underlying major principles, the concept and reality of "vital 54 The Invention of i\frica force" (set, e,g,, 1Viataczynski, 19 84 and Donders, 19 8 5 ), This outlook i.s Siimply a new mmrmer of demonstrating and promoting the essence of orthodoxy, the aim remaining dearly the same: "Christianity is the only possible conslu11mation of the B:mtu ideal" (Tempels, 1959:186). lempels is not alone in looking for nevv policies for integrating Christianity into African cultures, and Ethiopian Christianity, .African Islam and syncretic churches all over the continent witness to the vitaliiy of a process of indigenization (Monteil, 1980; Sundkler, 1964; Barrett, 1968; Brenner, 1984). Kn the 1960s, Taylor detected three main ingredients in the African challenge to Christianity: (a) Christian religion is "inherently ';ii/estern" and "fails to correspond to the felt needs of Asia and Africa"; (b) This challenge poses a radical question: "can the Christian faith nol: only prove its ability to meet the deep human needs of our time but also make peoples of different backgrounds feel at home in the new world?"; (c) "The Christian Church has not yet faced the theological problem of 'co-existence' with other religions" (Taylor 1963:6-8). At any rate, the apparent success of Christianity is startling. After one century of evangelizarion, the Christian community represents today some forty-five percent of the population of the continent, Let us not,: that, according to the World Bank (1984), the total population of sub-Saharan Africa, which "rose from 270 :nillion in 1970 to 359 million in 1980, seems set to double by the turn of the century and significantly more than triple by the year 2020" (World Bank, 1984:26). \lVithin this frame, the Catholic church has today some seventy-si1; minion members, Protestam denominations acknowledge fifty million followers; the Ethiopian Coptic church, thirty million members, 2nd some thousand autonomous local churches bring the total Christian membership to roughly 200 miHion. When one keeps in mind that, thrcugh conversion, and especially disproportionate population growth (see \l.'/orld Bank, 1984:82-83), the Christian community gains between five and s:x million new members each year, it becomes obvious that by the year 2000 Africa could have the largest concentration of Christians in the world (Barrett, 1970; 1V1eester de Ravenstein, 198oa::u5; Donders, 1985:1, 30). The trend is identical with the increase :n the number of ministers. A 198 5 Vatican statistical report shows that in Catholicism "the number of Diocesan clergy is increasing in Africa, South America and Oceania," fa Central America, the fig,~1rerse main "almost the sam::." In North America,, the rep01t notes a "modest drop," and "the most notable reduction [is] found in Europe." But the most significant shift is in the percentage of the world's major seminarians produced by different parts or the world. In Africa it jumped from 6.7 percent in 1973 to 10.7 percent in 1983, while in North America it ciropped to 10.9 percent from 19.2 percent in the same period. In Europe, the percent2.ge went down to 34.4 percent from 41.1 percent. If European Catholicism seems to be aging dangerously, the dyrn:unism of its African cmmterpart belongs either to a holy nightmare or, if one prefers, to an incredible miracle: monasteries are being built; new religious moveThe PovJer of Speech 55 ments, both activist and charisrnatic, are appearing and organizing themselves successfully; there are not enough schools for potential catechists, nor 2re there sufficient convents for nuns. There is not enough room in seminaries for candidates to the priesthood, yet despite the increase in vocation, particularly in the cmmtries with the highest fertility rates--Kenya, Nigeria, Tanzania, Za1re-the nmnber of priests is considered to be iow. According to the Vatican statistical document menti.oned above, in 1983 Europe had 58.2 percent of the world's priests for 3 3. 3 percent orth e ,.;;rorld'sC atholics; l'forth America had I 7" I percent of the world's priests for 7. 7 percerri: of its Catholic:s; South Americ.1 had 8.4 percent of the world's priests for 28.1 percent of the world's Catholics; and Africa lhad 4.3 percern: of priests for eight percent of the world's Catholics (see also Laurentin, 1977; Meester de Ravenstein, 198oa:214). As to other Christian denominations, one notes that, for example, the most populous Quaker community in the world lives in the northern part of Kenya, and that it is in Uganda that one finds the most statiscically important Anglican church in the world. The question becomes: how really Christian is this converted Africa? A. Hastings proposes a vague, prudent answer: As regards Catholics and Anglicans, [the Christian] advance could probably be charted in a mugh but not unreliable way by the decline in ecclesiastical marriage rates. Its vast, amorphous mass of devotion, cult, beiie~ superstition, new bonds of fellowship so often structured in ways that hardly accord with the rules of Rome, Geneva or Canterbmy, may prove the most enduring ecdesiastical legacy of this quarl:er century. (Hastings, 1979:27 4) This evduation does not ansvFer the question, nor does it explain why Christianirt seems so attractive. 1n his book on a Non-Bourgeois Theology, (1985), Donders emphasizes the appeal of the mirade of God in Jesus and the desire to be a memb":r of a new communitas or communion (see also Oduyoye 1986:97-108). He also refers to a cultural reason: the necessity of an anthropological conl!'ersion. David Barret believes that one of the main reasons Africans are so attracted to Christianity (and to Islam) is the community it offers" his his opinion that the conversion movemen~ 2.t the grassroots level is due to the fact that Africans are turning away from their local tribal religions because they see no "salvation" in those organizations anymore. They want to belong to a larger human and religious communit'j. (Donders, 1985:32) fo, fact, this seems like Baeta's dassi.cal explanation: "the mission station was no: merely a base for teaching the Christian d.iscipl.ine ... and for propagating the Faith: it was also the pocket of [a] new invading civilization" (1968:15). In a critical analysis of African Christianity, de Meester de Ravenstein nzmes three antinomies: the complexity of the African critique of ';J{?:estern The Invention of Africa Christianity, which implies the possibility of 21 zero degree of Christianiiy; the diffic;,dty of bringing together African "traditional" values and the absolute gratuity of God':s gifr; and the fondamental opposition ben-veen Christ's religion :md the African's religious heritage (198oa:43-50). These evaluations from knowledgeable observers dearly show the confusing reality of African Christianity. Let us foHow its recent history. Fro111t he 19 50s onward, new orientations appeared for the indigeni.zation of the Church (Nyamliti, 1978; Hastings, 1979). Gradually; official policies shifted from the initial step of adaptation, one that insisted on the Africani.zatio: i of some e.xternal aspects (music, hymns, etc.), t0 an examination of the content of Christianity ln an African setting. New premises established a completel.y different perspective: the "pagan culture" is considered and analyzed as an. abandoned field in 'Nhich Gcd's signs already exist (figure 4), Thus, if there can be only one aim-Christianity-methods are arbitrary and should be modified and adapted to circumstances and cultures (Taylor, 1963: 124). African intellectuals appealed "ta the Church to 'come to grips' with traditional practices, and with the world view that these beliefs and pracrices imply" (Hastings, 1979:119; see also Kalu, 1977). The best illustrations of this carrent are Gravrand's Visage africain de l'eglise (1962), Mulago's Un visage africain du christianisme (1965), Bahoken's Clairieres metaphysiques africaines (1967), and Mbiti's New Testament Eschatology in an African Bachground (1971). In these contributions, the authors explicitly favor the search for Christianity's essential message, one which would penetrate African ways of thinking and living. A new vocabuLuy arises and, in principle, covers nevv forms of evangelization: Africanization, indigenization, naturalization, ad2,ptation of Christianity, Some theorists even speak of "indigenizing the Gospel" and "the Message" CBimwenyi, 198rn:23:r). In Roman Catholic circles, the norms of the ne..v policy are relatively wdl spelled out in two official documents of Plus XH; Ev12ngelii Praecones (1951) and Fidei Donurn (1957). VJhai: this ambivalem: vc,cabulary introduces and means is a progn:ssive displacement of responsibili1y insofar as the future of Christianity is concerned (see, e,g,, Chipenda, 1977 and Setiloane, 1977). Hitstorically; one can refer to Des Pretres noirs s'interrogent (1956), a collection of black priests' articles and a solidly nationalist reflection on Christianity, as the first explicit manifestation of a new radical current. Ironically, it was during this period that positive and sympathetic •contributions on African religions were produced in anthropology. They include Deschamps's Les Religions d'A;frique noire ( I 9 5 4 ), Parrinder's African Traditional Religion ( 1 9 5 4 ), and Witchcraft (1558), Lienhardt's Divinity and Experience (1961), Van Caeneghein's La Notion de Dieu chez les Ba!ubas du Kasai· (1956), Schebesta's Le Sens religieu:c des primitifs (1963), Damann's Les religions de l'Alrique (1964, a translation of his 1963 Die Religionen Afrilzas), and Africa,: Systems of Thought edited by Fones and Dieterlen ( 196 5 ), }1.frican clergymen read these books looking for ways of transforming traditional religion or, at least, of The Power ol Speech 57 figure 4. The The Rligenization both at the durability of the founding arguments and at processes purifying controversial assumptions in the field. I have read three rewarding and ambitious contributions: 0. Nduka's brief essay on the implications of African traditional systems of thought, which is based on a "critique of principles of causation and the quality of the understanding of mechanical and organic processes" (Nduka, 1974:97); Gyekye's note on the philosophical relevance of Akan proverbs and the paradigm of the African proverb as situational (Gyekye, 1975); and l\Tkombe's impressive work on paremiologic symbols (1979). Using the logic of classes in order to des;cribe metaphors and metonyms in Tetela proverbs, l'~kombe succeeds in two ways: first, he makes an original contribution by demonstrating that it is possible to reformulate the logic of classes in terms of the logic of propositions; second, through this highly abstract exercise, he ana1yzes the originality of an African culture in i.ts dual dimension----internal plenitude and aspiration towards universality. A final example taken from a quite different source is Horton's schema of common and contrasting features existing bet 0wee11 African traditional thought and v(/estem science. At the end of his demonstration, he writes: "Though K largely disagree with the way in v1hich the 'I'-Tegritude' theorists have characterized the differences betvvee.n traditional Africaa and modern Westen-i. thought, when it gets to this point I see dearly what they are after" (1981:170). To sum up my position more theoretically, 1 would say that there i.s a mutation which took place in the 1920s and vvhich explains both the possibility and the pertinence of an African discourse on otherness, This mutation signifies a new foundation for organizing a plurality of historical memories within the frame of the same episteme. Thus, fundamentally, it does not seem to m.atter whether Herskovits\, propositions on African cultures, Vansina's methodological proposal on oral history, or Davidson's contributions to }',frican history and Balandier's to African sociology created or determined the emergence of a nevv spirit against a reigning trndition. It does not mean either that, before the 1930s, no one thought of questioning the grids through 'Which rhe Same displayed its kingship. R Blyden's thought, ) The Power of Speech 81 which I shall look at carefully below, is, for instance, an annunciating sign of the rupture. On the other hand, the very fact that in the 1930s and 1940s a Collingwood could concern himself with the theme of reenacting the glory of the Same by focusing on the documentary virtues of historical thought and its means does not invalidate my thesis. On the contrary, it rather shows the intellectual audacity of Herskovits or of Vansina, and its specificity as a question about both philosophical and historical imagination. The articulation of this mutation was already visible in the 1920s, and one of its most apparent signs is the fragmentation of the notion of civilization (see, e.g., Braudel 1980:177-217). In the first quarter of this century, critical thinkers like Blyden and Frobenius seemed to be simply transferring doxological modalities from their own rationalizations of African experiences; the first hypothesizing a black personality culture on the basis of the most controversial racist recommendations, the second anxious to grant African social formations the practicality of a classification of its culturally distinct features. However, it seems clear that Blyden and Frobenius, however unknowingly, participated in a larger epistemological shift. In the 1920s, this shift would, among other things, reveal its presence through the appearance of ideologies of existence, subjectivity, otherness, and interest in "oral philosophies" and histories. Picasso and Cendrars's celebration of primitive imagination and works, and Schmidt's description of the universal extension of an Urmonotheismus were predicated upon this epistemological shift, which makes them comprehensible. The specific question of African culture is probably the best conceivable illustration of this epistemological mutation. Within the framework of the early twentieth-century epistemology, all discourses on alterity could only, as Foucault suggested, be commentaries or exegeses on excluded areas: primitive experience, pathological societies, or non-normal functionality, subsumed by the Same defined and understood in terms of a biological model from which determining terms-function, conflict, signification--emerge as classifiers with the power of measuring the social, individual, or psychological distance vis-a-vis the model (see Foucault, 1973:360). Anthropology, as well as missionary studies of primitive philosophies, are then concerned with the study of the distance from the Same to the Other. A reversal of categories is more obvious in Schmidt's enterprise than in Malinowski's postulations. The former, by the extension of diffusionist gradients and thus the universalization of properties of the Same, was, despite his preconceptions, marking the very possibility of a grid which, using new criteria-rule, norm, and system-could eventually account for the universality and the particularity of each cultural organization according to its own rationality and historical strategies. And we have seen that the outcome of this problem in the 1950s depends on a new manner of speaking about theodicies and cosmogonies, which in their differences grant a regional coherence and at the same time witness to properties of human mind and its universal potentialities. On the other hand, the so-called relativist principles of Malinowski seem to be just The Invention of Africa sophisticated postulates which, coecretely, in the particularity of social formations as radically autonomous bodies with respect to their fo11ctional organization, negated cross-cultural influences, or at any rate the validity of any comparative schema, i\/Lore important, 1v1alinowski enclosed the alterit\J of social formations in their 0wn strictly limited otherness and dms very clearly :mderlined the regional virtues of such paradigms as function, coniqict, and signification. Thus it is no -.vond,~r that Malinowski's best creation was applied anthropology, a technique for supposedly avoiding aberrant mixtures of the Sanrne and the Other. The monstrosity is represented by a mixture "symptomatic and symbolic of rnhure change: the shokian, the famous concoction brev,red, retailed, and consumed in the notori.rn1s slum yards of native South African locations . . . Anything vvhich quickly incn:: ased the alcoholic content 'I/Vasa dded; calciurn carbide, methylated spiiits, tobacco, molasses and sugar, blue stone, are only a few examples" (.M:alinovvski, 1938:xxi). Independently from the significance of this violent symbol-- how can anyone, even an African., survive after drinking such a poison?-•if we carefully look at the paradigms which produce Malinawski's method and vvhich, essentially, are the same that guided applied anthropology, we can state th2.t there is no epistemological rupture between Levy-Bruhl's co!'mnents on prelogism and Malinowski's functionalism. All of them, s,s wdl as Durkheim (one of the guiding stars of functionalism) work at describing the reversed image of the Same through the models that impose the notions of function, conflict, and signification. The real change, that is, a reversal of grids, came later, Yet we have to note a major difference between Levy-Bmhl and Malinov, rski. The French philosopher is strictly concerned with the notion of deviation ( ecart) and, timmgh a:1 exegesis of merits of the Same's function and signification, he challenges the identity of human nature through time and space. As everym1e knovl/s, Levy-Bmhl was haunted by Tylor's theory about animism and Comte's Loi des trois hats. He used "primitives" as an opportunity for distinguishing both tbe logical and the historical distance that separates the homogeneous experience of the Same from the heterogeneity and prelogicaJ character of the Other. Malinowski, in contrast, was more imaginative, despite the fact that he belie-ved, as Levy-Bruhl did, that hEmans can be mere objects of science. He substituted the concept of an organic function of a social system for the determinis:m of the passage from prdogic to logical knovvledge, In doing so, MaHnowski was promoting a radical possibility, that of u.sing and referring to such conceptual tools as autonomous rule, social norm, and the epistemology and singularity of regional cultural systems. It becorn.es dearer that the voices which, from the 1920s to the r95os spoke against the historicity of the Same and its scientism do indeed repudiate anthropological policies and researches that are "anti-historical" insofar as Afri.can communities are concerned. Particularly, they oppose the political processes of acculturation (see V-/allerstein, :t983), Jn order to escape thes,c The Power of Speech ideological limits, some of the participants prudently or boldiy chose w claim that everything in human experience was simultaneously both culture and history. They were just inferring lessons of an epistemological mutation from the margins of Malinovvski's outlook. In effect, this rupture has led from an indecent curiosity about the mysteriousness of rhe Orher to P. Veyne's statement (to which Herskovits, Levi-Strauss, Vansina, Ajayi, or Cheikh Anta Diop could have subscribed): "the Romans existed in a manner just as exotic and just as ordinary as the Tibetans or the Nambibvara, for example, neither more nor less; so that it becomes impossible to continue to consider them as a sort of value-standard" (in Ricoeur, 1984:4.3). The Panacea of Otherm:ss J.-P. Sartre as an African Philosopher Apes ... descend from men? Some of us thought so; but it is not exactly that. Apes and men are two separate branches that have evolved from a point in common but in different directions ... P. BoULLE, Planet of the Apes. Up to the 1920s, the entire framework of African social studies was consistent with the rntionale of an epistemological field and its sociopoHtical expressions of conquest. Even those social realities, such as art, languages, or oral literature, which might have constituted an introduction to otherness, were repressed in support of theories of sameness. Socially, they were tools strengthening a new organization of power and its political methods of reduction, namely, assimilation or indirect rule. V'/ithin this context, negritude, a student movement that emerged in the 1930s in Paris, is a literary coterie despite i.ts political implications. Besides, these young menAime Cesaire, Leon Damas, Leopold Senghor--mostly used poetry to explore and speak about their difference as blacks (Blair, I 976: 14 3-51; Kesteloot, 19 6 5 ), his Sartre who in 1948 with his essay, Blac.k Orpheus, an introduction to . Senghor's Anthology of New Negro and Malagasy Poetry, transformed negritude into a major political event and a philosophical criticism of colonialism, However, everyone would agree that the Indian criticism of colonialism, beginning in the 1920s, and the growing influence of Marxism from the 1930s onwards opened a new era and made way for the possibility of ne,v i-ypes of discourses, v,-hich from the coloniai perspective v,ere both absurd and abhorrent. The most original include the negritude movement, the fifth Pan-African Conference and the creation of Presence Africaine. Eventually, these signs of an African vvill for power led to political ZJ.nd The fovention of ltfrica intellectual confrontations (Conferences of Bandung, P:His, and Rome). !n the 19 5 os, one also witnessed a radical criticism of anthropology and its inherenc preoorn:epti.ons of non-Western cultures. Since then, a stimulating debate about the African significance of social sciences and humanities has taken place, In his foreword to Senghor's anthology, J.-P. Sartre made the voices of negritude widely known. But what an ambiguity in raising the French existentialist to the rank of philosopher of negritude! The resources and promise of a young ideology devoting itself to the needs of a self-rediscovery were to be cast into a very critical but somehow stultifying mold. In Black Orpheus, Sartre presents n1eans for a struggle against the dominant ideology and affirms the right of Africans to fashion a new mode of thought, of speech, and of life. ~/hat he proposes is much more than a brilliant game of opposites (with which Senghor might have been satisfied). "Today, these black n1en have fixed their gaze upon us and our gaze is thrown back in our eyes; black torches, in their turn, light the world and our white heads are only sma.11 lanterns balanced in the wind" (1976:7-8). Sartre goes further, With passion, he sets up paradigms that would allow the colonized black to assume control of a self (see Jeanson, 1949). "It is the efficiency alone which counts." "The oppressed class must first take conscience of itself." "This taking of conscience is exactly the opposite of a redescent into one's sdf; it has to do here with a recognition in and action of the objective situation of the proletariat." "A Jew, white among white men, can deny that he is a Jew, can declare himself a man among men. The Negro cannot deay that he is Negro nor claim for himself this abstract uncolored humaniiy." Sartre even specifies the exact significance of the Negro's revolt: The Negro who vindicates his negritude in a revolutionary movement places himself, then and there, upon the terrain of Reflection, whether he wishes to rediscover in himself certain objective traits growing out of African civilization, or hopes to find the black Essence in the wells of his souL (Sartre, 1976:17) The negritude which he thus affirms and celebrates is simultaneously the "triumph of J',Tarcissism and suicide of Narcissus, tension of the sou1 outside of its culture, words and every psychic fact, luminous night of non-knowledge." Immediately after this celebration, he warns that negritude can neither be sufficient nor must it live forever. It is made to be negated, to be exceeded. Among the ruins of the colonial era, its singers must again rework songs, reformulate their myths, and submit them to the service and to the need of the revolution of the proletariat. It could be said of Black Orpheus that while correcting the potential theoretical excesses of the ideology of negritude, it did so in a high-handed manner, thwarting other possible orientations cf the movement. At the same time, it subjugated. the militants' genercsity of heart and mind to the fervour of a political philosophy. Sartre, in the 1940s and early 1950s, was promotThe Power of S;/Jeech ing, in the name of commitment, the moral demand of choosing political sides. A substantial part of Being and Nothingness is devoted to the tension between the for itself (pour-soi) and for others (potu--autrui). 1',Jow Sartre dedicated himself to the analysis of the concrete consequences of this dialecric as iHustrated by colonial syst,ems (Sartre, 1956). It was i:o the credit of Senghor that he was not stifled by the peremptory arguments and the vision of this first theoretician of negrimde whom he had aroused: he had asked Sartre for a doak to celebrate negritude; he was given a shroud. Nevertheless, Blade Orpheus is a major ideological moment, perhaps one of the most important. h displays both the potentialities of Marxist revolution and the negation of colonialism and racism: "The Negro," states Sartre, "creates an anti-racist racism. He does not at all 'Nish to dominate the world; he wishes the abolition of racial privileges wherever they are found; he affirms his solidarity with the oppressed of aU colorn. At a blow the subjective, existential, ethnic notion of Negritude passes as Hegel would say, into the objective, positive, exact notion of the proletariat" ( r 976: 5 9 ). What Sartre did was to impose philosophically the political dimension of a negativity in the colonial history. This was a compeUing task for Africans. By emphasizing the relativity and the sins of \Y/estern expansionism, he gave meaning and credibility to all signs of opposition to colonialism and called for a new understanding of the significance of violence in the colonies. Thus, Pan-African Conferences, Gandhi's noncooperation movement, and the NeoDestur party emerging in Tunisia would appear to have a dialectical and positive portent for the future: they could influence the lives of the colonized and, also fundamentally, provide the possibility of new societies. The change from colonized to independent, from rule by divine right to liberation, may not seem to have any relation to anthropology in particular or African social studies in general. In fact, it does. First, Black Orpheus was in large measure responsibl.e for the blossoming in Francophone Africa of the negritu.de literature of the 1950s (Blair, 1976; Wauthier, 1964). A litterature engagee, a highly political literature, put forward Sartre's basic positions concerning African spiritual and political autonomy. This new generation of writers born bet\:11een 1910 and 19:w includes Cheikh Anta Diop, Bernard Dadi,~, Rene Depestre, Frantz Fanon, Keita Fodeba, Camara Laye, and Ferdinand Oyono, among others. Second, black intellectuals, particularly Francophones, read Sartre, discussed his anticolonialist positions and, generally speaking, upheld them. Fanon disagrees with Sartre yet offers a good example of his impact. In his Peau noire, masques blancs, fanon accuses Sartre of treason, for fanon does not believe that "Negritude is dedicated to its own destruction." Some years later, in Les Damnes de la terre, the 'Xlest Indian theorist firmly applies Sartre's dialectical principle and bluntly states: "there wiH not be a Black culture," "the Black problem is a political one." On the other hand, there is a connection between this black litterature engagee and the African ideology of otherness. In Black Orpheus Sartre proposes a Marxist paradigm. The founders of negritude do not disagree 86 The fovention of Afri,ca with him on this point, Some 'V/est Indians, for instance Aime Cesaire, Etienne Lem, JuLes Monnerot, and Jacques f{omnain, have been at one tin1.e or another E1embers of the Communist Party. 1Vfamadou Dia, Alioune Diop, Birago Diop, Jacques Rabemananjara, and Senghor are rather critical of communism, eve~1 when, as in the case oi Senghor, they are socialists. For them communism is merely (as Sartre defined it) a t.ravding companion, They question the overemphasis on the fate of rhe international proletariat and wish to determine a strategy for promoting the individuality of 1':..frican culture. As opposed to Marx's rigid interpretation of the relations berween values and peoples' aspirations in society, they look: for ways of reinventing a sociohistoric foundation for independent African societies (Senghor, 1962). Thus the basic premise of the African ideology of otherness: history is myth. lis Sartre really the inspired guide of this revolution? Let us say that Sartre, philosopher in partibus of negritude--or, figuratively, Sartre as "Negro philos: opher"-is a symboL Since the 192.os, writers like R.1v1aran, A. Gide, or M. Sauvage had criticized the colonial enterprise. In anthropology, scholars such as Maurice Delafosse, Leo Frobenius, J\ilarcel Griaule, and Theodore Monod had offered positive views of Africa!" social regimes. And in 19,1,7, we found grouped around the press and journal, "Presence Africaine" and its founder, Alioune Diop, a significant number of French intellectuals. Georges BaLmdier, Albert Camus, Emmanuel Mounier, Paul Rivet, Gide, and Monod, for example, affirm the polii:i.cal and cuh:urali implications of the mythical character of colonial history (Rabemananjara, s.d.:24). But Sartre established a cardinal synthesis. By rejecting both che colonial rationale and the set of culturally eternal. values as bases for society, his brief treatise posited philosophically 2 relativist perspective for African social studies. Sartre did not necessarily influence George Balandier or Joseph Ki-Zerbo nor does he guide all Africa~1 thinkers. Nevertheless, his i.nsight5 illuminated the trends and preoccupations of African scholarship" His path to liberation meant a new epistemological configuration under the sovereignty of dialectical reason (Jean.son, I 949 ). It is from his interpretation, rather than from communism, that the two characteristics of present-day African social studies presented by Copans (x97ra) make sense: on the one hand, a radical criticism of imperialism and, on the other, a "Marxist revival" which, in effect, has taken hold of the whole theoretical domain of African studies. Despite the importance of the negritude rnovement, very little attention has been given to the relationships between its textual organization, its sources, and its expressions (Melone, 1962). •We have known, for instance, ;:hat negritTt1de was a French invention but not how essentially French it vvas (Adotevi, 1972). We have been told that the negritude literature appears unified, but its structure and spirit are more in keeping with European sources than with immediately visible African themes (Gerard, 1964; Bastide, 1961). Hauser's voluminous book (1982) deals with these issues and is probably the n1ost complete study to date on the negritude movement. The value of this work does not lie in any new discovery but in the manner in The .Power of Speech which it addresses the issues of negritude's significance and objectives, According to Sartre, negritude signifies, fundamentally, tension between the black man's past and future. Thus ii: must always be ready to redefine itself. As Hauser says, it clothes itself in mythical forms offering its meaning as a mot de passe and its philosophy as an inversion and a reversal of '\JVestern theses. The result is a paradox: "Poets for the Blacks, the men of the Negritude movement vvere read by '\Whites; Poets of the present, they are perceived in Africa as poets of the past" (Hauser, 1982.::2,1;.1). While a literary language., negritude's content reveals an ideological system and even, according to Sartre, "a revollltionary project." It comments upon a Weltanschauung, interprets a given world, unveils the universe (dire le monde), and gives a significance w it (signifier le monde) (Melone, 1562; Diakhate, 1965), JBut at the same time, because it is an ideological discourse, negritude daims to be a key to a nevv understanding of history, And thus the problen1 of the political and cultural responsibility of the negritude movement (Senghor, 1964) appears as a responsibility ·which Hauser considers ambiguous, Insofar as negritude's political position is concerned, Hauser states that negritude has not been a revolutionary movement nor even, with the exception of Cesaire, a movement of revolt (Hauser, 1982:4-4-3). Moreover, in relation to its conditions of possibiHti;; negritude stands as the result of multiple influences: the Bible, anthropologists' books, and French intdlectual schools (symbolism, romanticism, surreal.ism, etc.), literary legacies, and literary models (Baudelaire, Lautreamont, Rimbaud, Mallarme, Valery, Claude!, St, John Perse, ApoHinaire, etc.), Hauser presents multiple proofs of the \Y/estern souc:oes of negritude and seriously doubts its African authenticity (Hauser, 1982:533), It becomes imm.ediately apparent from these internal contradicti.ons of negritude chat Sartre's proposition on the deadlock of the movement makes tremendous sense, Unless understood as metaphors, the signs of otherness that negritude might have promoted in literature, philosophy, history, or social science, seem to refer to techniques of ideological manipulation. R Depestre forcefully points this out, The original 5in of negritude-and the adventures that destroyed its initial project--come from the spirit rhat made it possible: anthropology, The crisis that destroyed negritude coincides with the winds that blow across the fields in vvhich anthropology-be it cultural, social, applied, structural-with black or white masks, is used to carqing out its learned inquiries. (Depestre, 1980:83) ldeologies fur Otherness In the wake of negritude, but also running paraHel to it or even against it, is the affirmation of African political thought. It aimed initialJy ,1t recognizing the black personality (la personalite negre) and obtaining certain sociopolitical rights (W/authier, 1964). Only later, in the 1950s, did it really 88 The invention of Africa serre projects for African independence (Coquery-Vidrovitch, 1974). It is commonplace to see in it one of the important elements of African na 0 tionalis0. The orher is resistance co colonialism, whether passive or violent. It is notevvmthy that its most distinguished promoters are drawn from among those first and best assimilated to Western culture and thoughto Further, one almost senses that i:hese 'l;xlesternized Africans resented the need to retura to rheir own sources and to state the right to be different ( see Kesteloot, 19 6 5; Wauthier, 1964; Dieng, 1983\ To consider this awakening as a special turning point in the history of the \Vest is nof, in any case, to disqualify it. In I 9 5 7, Nkrumah published his autobiography, in which h,c: explained to what extent he had been influenced by communist and socialist v1ritings, Black American political theories (particularly 11/farcus Garvey's Philosophy c;nd Opinions), and Padmore's vievv on Pan-Africanismo He also wrote that he learned much from Hannibal, Cromwell, Napoleon, Mazzini, Gandhi, Mussolini, and Hitler. Senghor (1962) aRso presented his own orientation, writing in first-person plural to indude his friends, the co-founders of the negritude movement. If they believed in affirming their difference, it was, according to him, because of ;mthropologists and Black Americans. Also, in the period between the two wars they were privileged witnesses of the crisis of Western values. lvforeover, their recent discovery of 1V1arx gave them reasons for utopian dreams. Senghor's explanation is plausible. Up to the 1960s, anthropology, Black American ideology, and Marxism had a significant impact on the African intelligentsia. For the sake of brevity, let us mention as important points of reference rhree major types of contributions which gradually changed colomial thinking and practice. First, there were anthropological ano missionary commitments to African values: for instance, Schmidt's enterprise in the r93os, and Tempels's, Griaule's, and Danquah's studies in the 1940s. In addition, contributions from African scholars such as Mulago ( I 9 5 5 ), and Kagame (1956), promoted the concept of African theodicy or of signs of a natural religion. They all established African religions as particular and original experi,ences of a universal wisdom or philosophy. Second, there was intervention by some "Western sociologists and historians. Raymond Michelet in his African Empires and Civilizations ( 194 5) and :Basil Davidson and Georges Bdandier in their numerous publications opposed widely accepted conceptions of "living fossils" or "frozen societies," Third, there was the '\rwakening" of African intellectuals who began to speak abou,t their past and their culture and attacked, or at least interrogated, colonialism and its basic principles (Dieng, 1979; Guisse, 1979). This ideological rupture sounds sincere and quite probably was in the mi!1ds of scholars who participated in it. Yet, it is a magnificent paradox, an almost iUusory sacrifice of applied anthropologyo It is based on two fragile principles: a methodological reversal and an inteHectual discontinuinJ in African social studies. In their application, rather than opening up a new realm, these principles helped to confuse prospects for otherness and the The Power of Speech significance of this concept. The significance belongs to the studied Other and is re,realed to perception and given to understanding through the reality of a concrete experience. As to the discourse on this significance, it is always a project and a transcendenr idea which cannot be reduced to a mental apprehension, To teach, as did Danquah, Davidson, Michelet, or l\Aulago, that there are, in Africa, organized social stmctures, sophisticated systems of rdati.ons of production, 2nd highly complex universes of belief, is to express pmpositions 'which can be tested. To add commentaries or exegeses on black cultures which are essentially mystical, religious, and sensuous, is to decipher a possibly controversial myth and, at any rate, to elaborate on v.rhat is not the immanent significance of the object studied, The anthropologist did not seem to respect the irnmanence of human experience and went on to organize, at scientific expense, methods and ways of ideological reduction: concrete social experiences were looked at and interpreted from the normativity of a political discourse and its initiatives. With a Michelet and a Herskovits, the forming of new ideological perspectives in the field produced a reversal: African experiences, attitudes, and mentalities became mirrors of a spiritual and cultural richness. There is no mystery, nor scandal in this, if we agree that we are dealing with discourses bearing upon human experience and accounted for by an episteme. K should also make it dear again that we are not concerned with evaluating the ethical value of discourses, but only with designating a genealogy of knowledge, 1\1ichelet's, Davidson's, Balandier's or Mulago's studies do not transform the heart of the object matter, but rather reverse, as Sartre did philosophicaHy, a method of narrntion and the techniques of describing the object. A shift has occurred. A nevv anthropology has, silently but powerfully, put in place its basic norms, namely respectability and internal coherence for African systems and experience, as well as rules for their progressive integration into modernity. One may observe this gradual. change in some representative domains: anthropology, history, and political thinking. In anthropology, studies of traditional laws were carried out by A. Ajisafe, The Laws and Customs of the Yoruba People (1924-), and J. B, Danquah, Akan Laws and Customs (1928). Analyses of African customs were published; for example, D. Delobson's, Les secrets des sorciers noirs (1934), I\/L Quenum's, .Au Pays des Fons: us et coutumes du Dahomey (1938), J, Kenyatta's, Facing Mount Kenya (1938), J.B. Danquah, The Akan Doctrine of Goel ([1944] 1968), and the exce!Jent researches of :IC A. Eusia and P. Hazoume, respectively, The Position of the Chief in the Modern Political System of Ashanti ( r 9 5 r) a:nd Le pacte du sang au Dahomey ( [ r 9 3 7] r 9 5 6). In the field of history, the most prominent contributions to African nationalism were J. C. de GraftJohnson's African Glory: The Story of Vanished Negro Civilizations (1954) and Cheikh Anta Diop's, Nations negres et culture (1954), in vvhich he analyses the notion of Hamites and the connections between Egyptian and African languages and civilizations. The Invention of Jl,.frica h vlas i.n the poliii:ic2.le ssays drnt a clearly progressive awakening gradually affirmed the principles of African nationalism and international integration. Kn Towards Nationhood in West Af·rica (1928), J. W. de Graft-Johnson still envisz.ged the future af West Africa in terms of the British Empire. But nine years later, 'YI. Azikiwe, in Renascent Africa (1937), was more critical of \'!Vestem colonial programs. He emphasized the fact that the "renascent African'' must know that his ancestors "made definite contributions to history" and he condemned im.perialism and militarism. lvfajor essays too~( into account the resolution of the Fifth Pan-African Congress of Manchester (1945) which stated: "we demand for Blade Africa autonomy and independence," a central theme i.n Nkrumah's Towards Colonial Freedom (1947), Cesaire's Discours sur le colonialisme (1950), and fanon's Peau noire, masques blancs (1952). For a rnunber of African intellectuals, i:hese v,orks have been, and probably stiH are, major sources for their cultural autonomy. fo her doctoral dissertation (1965), L Kesteloot provided a brief history of the contacts w:ith Black Americans that contributed to the awakening of the consciousness of Africans (see also Shepperson, 1960). L G. Damas, just before his death in 1978, strongly confirmed this thesis vvith reference to the contributions of Y/J. E. B, DuBois, Langston Hughes, Carter Woodson, Countee Cullen, and, in particular, J\1ercer Cook, all of whom he considered links between Black Americans and Africans (Damas, 1979:2,p-54). To these names, Senghor adds Claude MacKay and Richard \Vright (Senghor, r962). It i.s difficult to say with certainty to i.vhat extent the ideological commitment of Black Americans made an impact on the African intelligentsia. It converged with the influence of the llviarxist movement and particularly with that of the French Communist Party which, before World War H, was the force best organized to fight openly for the black man's cause. A number or Francophone black inteHectuals became communists, including Cesai.re, J. Romnain, E. Lero, and J. S. Alexis. Others, like Nkrumah, Nyerere, and Senghor, allied themselves with socialist ideological principles. In any case, the association ''Nith Black Ameri.cms strongly influenced the critical views of bfack Africans v1ith respect to the crisis of Western values. h also revealed differences in the sociohistorical conditions of both. Opposition had already appeared at i:he Second Pan-African Congress, in 1921, held successively in London (August 28), Brussels (August 2,9-September 2), and Paris (September 3 and 5 ). Surveying the history of the black race, DuBois had, to Blaise Diagne's great surprise, pleaded for the principle of the separation of races and of separate evolution. But Diagne imposed on the assembly the ethnological point of view that "the Black and the colored people were capable of progressive development which would aHow [ them 1 to reach the advanced state ot otiher races" (Bontinck, 1980:604-605). Nevertheless, the greatest influence on African thought from the 1930s to the 1950s was lVfarxism. Significant examples of its impact are the 1warm support that Sartre gave to the negritude movement in 1948 with his essay, The Power of S;tJeech 91 Biack Orpheus, the publication by Aim§ Cesaire of Dfrcours sur le coloniaiisrne in 1950, and the meeting at the Sorbonne, in 1956, of the Flrst International Congress of Black 1JVriter:sa rid Artists, That same year some black intellectuals stated publicly that they wished that Marxism could promote their cause, and not only the reverse. In frustration, Cesaire ( 19 5 6) left the French Communist Party. During the Sorbonne meeting, lVlarxism was at the center of the debate. A critical distance was therefore suggested, without entailing total rejection. A.s A. Ly ,ivould say, "the blind refusal of Marxism would be as cibsurd as a total alienation ~o the Iviarxist system would be fatal for the evolution of humankind" ( I 9 5 6), Though expressed differendy, it is this spirit that dominated the debates during the first meeting of nonaligned nationaHsts in Bandung. Ultimately, the principle of nonalignment would be projected in politics. En literature (see Jahn, 1968), this position is expressed in three msjor wsys: first, in terms of domestication of political pov,er (E. Mphahlele, Mongo Beti, and Sembene Ousmane); second, in a criticism of colonial life (Chinua Achebe, D. Chra:ibi, E Oyono); and third, in the celebration of the African sources of Hfe (A, Loba, A Sefrioui, Cheikh Hamidou Kane). h is noteworthy that a number of political leaders who came to power in independent l'l.frica declared themselves pro-Marxist or socialist or, in some cases, defined ways of indigenizing socialisr11. Socialists or not, the African heads of state, :attempting to link thought to action, have published r111Tch, perhaps too much. hi the late I 9 50s, one o1 the most prestigious leaders, Ahmed Sekou Toure, dared to refuse the progressive route to political autonomy proposed by France. In 19 5 9, he published n10re tha.11 a thousand pages on his socialist prcjects for the devdopment of Guinea ,md the promotion of Africa (1959a, 19596, 1959c). Aime Cesaire celebrated this "courageous" and "dynamic" thought (1959-1960). lin its inspiration, as in. its perspectives, it is dose to that of Nkruniah. 'With the translation 0£ his autobiography, Nkrumah's influence, alread1y immense in Anglophone Africa, can'le to French-speaking countries in 1960. His work met increasing favor, whose highest point was the welcome given to his Consciencism. In thi.s work, as in others, Nkrumah incorporated! fidelity to Marxism into the cause of decolonization and the struggle aga_inst imperialism. His friend Patrice Lumumba had neither the time to clarify his thought nor to refine his essays (1963) which appeared after his death. Sartre again put his talent to the service of }_frican nationalism by introducing J. Van Lierde's book on Lmnumba's political philosophy (Van U.erde, 1963). NPmerous other leaders expounded their points of vievv on the complex problems of independent Africa. The major issues concern the management of the State as vveH as the means for economic liberation. Such leaders include Ahidjo in Cameroon (196.4, 1969), Badian in Mali (1964), 1Vfamadou Dia in Senegal (1957, 1960), and Kanza in the Belgian Congo (1959a, 1959b). Nyerere in Tanzania has promoted ujamaa (communalism) (1968a) and 11.1:t." ,Tgouabi (Congo) insisted on the necessity of applying scientific soThe Invention of Africa cialism (1975). But the paths taken in politics, yrhen they have not Led to bitter failure, have often caused serious problems. \Vhen permitted., political reaction surfaced. In any case, diHeren-:: scho:.,ls 0£ thought have arisen; hence, for exa.mple, the satire and the polemics found in D. Evvande's rr:.ockery of the Negro State (1968). These schools of thought were asserted in cathartic terms, especially in fiction in the I 970s, through attacks on the incompetence anc'. the abuses of the ne1N African administrators. The thene of ruthless colonial exploitation is replaced by an 0riginal sociopoHtical subject: "we are, in the main, to blame for our misfortunes" (Casteran and LangeHier, 1978; Pomonti, 1979). There is a proliferation of examples in the literary works of Kwei Armah, Kofi Awoonor, Cameron Duodu, Ahrnadou Kouromrna, Tierno j\fonenembo, Ngugi wa Thiongo, and Tati-Loutard. l\farx Africanized The political image of Africa after I 96 5 is indeed distressing. Authoritarian regimes ha¥e multiplied, rules and norms of democracy have been flouted or rejected (see Gutkind and 'JC!allerstein1,9 76; O'Meara and Carter, 1986). Political dictatorships have been imposed. Some charismatic leaders have vanished into obscurity. Toure was isolated in his dictatorship and Nkrumah, challenged and insulted, died in exile (Powell, 1984). Senghor remained a model. Yet he chose to remove IVfamadou Dia, his opponent, whose economic ideas were considered in the 1960s to be a necessary complement to Senghor's metaphysics of negritudeo He did this to guar;mtee security for the African path to socialism (Kacha1na-Nk:oy, 1963). Covered with honors, but criticized ;more and more by the new generation, Senghor struggled to make aU his v,orks accessible (1964, 1971, 1977, 1983). At the same time he continued, against aH opposition, to define negritude as a value of dialogue and of openness andi to clarify his humanist choices for socialist politics and for aa economy based on an African reading of Marx (1976a). Nyerere, in these years, also appears as one of the more credible political thinkers. Despite the crucial problems of its adaptation to the African context, socialism seemed the most fashionable docrrine. Its best known proponents are Fanon, Senghor and Nyerere. The VVest In.dian Frantz fanon, a solid lVfarxist, but also a good student of Hegel, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Sartre, expressed his commitment to the African revolution in Peau noire, masques bianc.s (1952), Les Damnes de la terre (1962), and Pour la revolution Africaine (1969). His cmnmitment is based on a concrete understanding of the Hegelian dialectic. The alienation caused by colonialism constitutes the thesis, the African ideologies of otherness (black personality and negritude), the antithesis, and political liberation should be the synthesis. The similarity with Sartre's analysis in Black Orpheus is striking. But Fanon, who was probably more concerned with detaiis and practical contradictions because he knew them better, had come from a "colony," was hin1self black, The Power of Speech 93 and participated actively in the Aigerian revolution, fo contrast to Sartre, he could address a vvider range of problems. The alienation of colonialism entails both the objective fact of total dependeP.. ce (economic, political, cultural, and religious) and the subjective process of the sel!i-victirnizati.on of the dominated. The colonized in:::ernalizes the imposed racial stereotypes, particularly in attitudes towards technology~ culture, znd language. Black personality and negritude appear as the only means of negating this thesis, and Fanon expounds the antithesis in terms of antiracist symbols. Negritude becomes the intellectual and emotional sign of opposition to the ideology of white superioriv;. At the same time, it asserts an authenticity which eventually expresses itself as a radical negation: rejection of racial humiliation, rebellion against the rationality of domination, and revolt against the whole colonialist system. This symbolic violence ultimately turns into nationalism and subsequently leads to a political struggle for liberation, The synthesis is the conjunction of, on the one side, "national consciousness" and "political praxis," and, on the other, the contradictions created by existing social dasses: national bourgeoisie, proletariat, underproletariat, and peasantry. '7/hereas Fanon distinguishes the analysis of a struggle for liberation (first phase) from the promotion of socialism (second phase) Senghor tends to define African socialism as just a stage in a complex process beginning with negritude and oriented towards a universal civilization. He emphasizes ::hree major moments: negritude, 11/farxism, and universal civilization. (a) Negritude is "the warmth" of being, living, and participating in a natural, social, and spiritual harmony. h also means assuming some basic political positions: that colonialism has depersonalized Africans and that therefore the end of colonialism should promote the seH-fulfillment of Afric: ms. Thus, negritude is simultaneously an existential thesis (l am what I have decided to be) and a political enterprise. fr also signifies a political choice: among European n1cthods, socialism seems the most useful for both cultural reassessment and sociopolitical promorion. (b) l'vfarxism is, for Senghor, a method. In order to use it adequately, the Senegalese thinker dissociates Marxism_ as humanism from lVfarxism as a theory of knov,ledge. The first offers a convincing explanation of the notion of alienation in its theory of capital and value and exposes the scandal of human beings under capitalism becoming mere means of production and strangers vis-a-vis the product of their work For this reason, Senghor readily accepts Marxism's conclusions insofar as they indicate a recognition of the natural rights of humans, who are and must remain free agents and creators of cu.lture. "We are socialist," writes Senghor, "because we accept 1'/farx and Engels and believe in the usefulness of their analysis of societies. Yet we add to 1VIarx and Engels' works the contributions of their successors." For Senghor, .Marxism as a theory of kncnvledge nevertheless constitutes a problem. It is one thing to use its schemas for analyzing and understanding the 94 The Invention of Africa complexity of social formations, and another ta accept the idea that social complexiries uni.versaHy fit into the concept of the class struggle and express the need to deny religion. ( c) Neg£itvde and M,uxi.st humanism are, according to Senghor, only stages in a dynamic dialectic process towards a universal civilization. Interpreting hypot:,eses of Piem: TeHhard de Chardin, Senghor bases his ideas of a universal civil!ization upon laws of evolution. He beHeves that the movement from. rnicmentities: to more complex ones and finally consciousness expresses a natural law. This would in1ply at least three major theses: che principle cl development of aH human beings, the principle of harmony in development, and God's existence as a natural necessity. Senghor thinks that some basic African values are well expressed in this perspective: namely the idea of community, the principle of harmony bet,;veen evolving humans and changing nature, and, finally, the vision or a unitary universe. Senghor's influence on contemporary African thought, particularly in Francophone countries, is cc,nsiderable. The Senegalese writer, like the Ghanaian Nkrumah, does not allow himself to be neutral. Of the African thinkers of this century, he will probably have been the most honored and the n10st complimented, yet probably also the most disparaged and the most insulted, particularly by the present generation of African intellectuals. Jt fa significant that S. Azombo-Menda and M. Anobo, in their manual of African philosophy, believe they are obliged to explain the presence of Senghor in their text. "His thought has exerted on black intellectuals such influence that it would be regrettable were his principal theses to be ignored or passed in silence by sectarianism or because people felt incapable to discuss them" (Azombo-Menda and Anobo, 1978). Does including Senghor in a textbook of African philosophy reaHy require excuses? It is fitting to note that Senghor has become a myth that is endlessly discussed. It is true that criticism, especially African, has mainly seen in Senghor the promoter of some famous oppositions which, out of context, could appear to embrace perspectives proper to certain racist theoreticians: Negro emotion confronting hellenistic reason; intuitive Negro reasoning through participation facing European analytical thinking through utilization; or the Negro-African, person of rhythm and sensitivity, assimilated. to the Other through sympathy, who can say "I am the other ... therefore I am." On this basis, Senghor has been accused of seeking to promote a dei0estable model for a di.vision of vocations between Africa and Europe, between African and European (e.g., Towa, 1971a; Soyinka, 1976). This seems quite vvrong. Senghor's philosophy can be simply linderstood through a challenging proposition he offered to the Senagalese Socialist Party in July 1963: "Finally, what too imany Africans lack, is the awareness of our povert'f and creative imagination, I mean the spirit of resourcefulness" (1983:152). :Nyerere's socialism is probably the most pragmatic of all African socialisms (Duggan and Civile, 1976:181). Its basic assumption has been The Power of Speech 95 spelled out in simple terms. ][n the expression "African soci2.Jism" the most important word is not socialism but A/rican. In other words, according to Nyerere, an African does not need to convert to socialism or to democracy, since his own traditional experience is socialist and democratic: The true African socialist does not look on one class of men as his brethren and another as his nat,1ral enemies. He does not form an alliance with the 'brethren' for the extermination of the 'non-brethren.' He regards all men as his brethren----2,s members of his ever-extending family. Ujamaa, then, or 'fami!ihood,' describes our socialism. (Nyerere, 1968a:27) Ujamaa, or comn:mnalism, rejects both capitalism (which "seeks to bu.ild a happy society on the basis of exploitatton of man by man") 8od doctrinaire socialism (which "seeks to build its happy society on a philosophy of inevitable conflict between man and man"). For Nyerere, ujamaa means first of all the creation of a new society, a nation, based on the traditional model of family. Second, moving beyond the nation, the socialist project would imply a constant development of communalism for all peoples (Duggan and Civile, 1976:188-96). The Arusha Declaration, issued by Nyerere's party in 1967, made Nyerere's program more explicit. It presented the party's creed, its socialist charter, the policy of self-reliance, the philosophy of membership, and an official statement about socialist leaders. The creed presents the rationale of ujamaa. Kn the first part, it describes the major values (sharing, equality, rejection of alienation and exploitation of man by man, etc.). In the second part, i,t offers as ideological deductions its main political objectives. These are: first, the independence of the nation, but a socialist nation governed by a socialist government; second, cooperation with African countries and commitment to the liberation of Africa and her unity; and third, improvement of the conditions of equality and life in the nation and, therefore, nationalization of the means of production and political control of the fields oif production. The search fur the construction of a nevv African society has also led in other directions. Both J\,t Azikiwe's interpretation of political unity and the pragmatic federalism advocated by n Awolowo in Path to Nigerian Freedom (1947) have followers. Nkrumah's political philosophy is still popular all over the continent, especially his concept of social revolution described in I Speak of Freedom (1961) and the materialism of Consoiencisrn (1970), which exposes a sociopolitical system implying dialogue and the possibility of reconciling antagonistic forces and orienting them towards positive social change. Unfortunately, looking back at Nkrumah's regime in Ghana, one might think that all was just rhetoric. Though a good 1\/Iarxist theorist, Nkrumah, once in power, became a bad politician and" rapidly turned into a dictator. The best that can be said is that he simply failed to put his theory into practice. Yet his theoretical legacy remains, challenging and stimulating The Invention of Afric2. for the nevv generndon of African Marxists looking for paradigms of revolutionary change and cultural dynamism. On 2 quite general levei, one may still admire his critical evalu.ati.on of G. Padmore's Panafri::anism or Communism, his 7ilews on the unity of th,~ continent, and the pertinence of hi.s analyses of neocolonialism (t,~krurnah, 1962, 1965). It is my feefo,,g that in general the nevv African trend concentrates on the idedogical significance of the failure of contemporary African society. !n French-speaking countries, the criticism is carried out in the context of present-day sociopolitical contradictions rooted in both the precolonial a"1d coioniaTI experience, as for example, by Pathe Diagne in Pouvoir polii-ique traditionnel en Afrique occidentale (1967) and G. L Hazoume with his book Ideologies t,ibalistes et nation en Afrique: le cas Dahomeen (1972). Under the circums'.:ances, many thinkers tend to reevaluate African socialism and insist on the usefulness of applying the Marxist lesson in a more systematic manner. Ivlajhemout Diop suggested this in his Contribution a l'etude des problemes politiques en Afrique noire (1958). Osende Afana briHiantly applied Marxist perspectives to the economic situation of '0Vest Africa irc L'Economie ouest-africaine. Perspectives de developpement (1967, 1976). The Marxist trend seems still to be dynamic, as shown by the writings of authors such as Diagne, Hountondji, and M. Ngouabi, as well as by the official ideological choices of the regimes of Angola, Benin, Congo, Ethiopia, and Mozambique. The newly created Journal of African Marxists is also an indication of the Marxist revival in Africa. It has succeeded in bringing together intellectuals from all over the continent and states its task in terms of "providing a platform for Marxist thought to provide that element most needed now to enable Africa to throw off imperialist domination and capitalist e..xploitation" (1983, no. 4:3; see also Dieng:1979). In contrast, and mainly in V'/est Africa, other scholars continue to give priority to questions that have been asked again and again about tradition. M. Dia, for instance, vvith his works on Islamic humanism (1977, 1979), joins lL Hampate Ba and Boubou Hama, prestigious survivors of an old team which, from the 1930s onward, has continued to invoke traditionalism and Islam as effective sources of regeneration (see also Brenner, 1984). Present trends give the impression that the Africa of the 1980s is reliving the crises of the 1950s, To create myths which would give a meaning to its hopes for improvemeat, Africa seems to hesitate between two principal sources, 1v1ar1dst and traditionalist, and to vvorry endlessly about the evidence abou';: the superiority of the Sarne over the Other and the possible virtues of the inverse relatjonship. But a discrete an.cl controverted current has quietly developed since 19 5 4, the date of the publication of Cheikh Anta Diop':;; Nations negres et culture. To rnany, this current appears as the only reasonable alternative co the present disorder, Using JVLarxism as a foil, it intends to study African tradition in depth, affirming the cultural unity of precoloni.al Africa, linguistic kinship, and common historic past (Diop, The Power of Speech 97 1954, 1960a, 1967, 1931). Diop\; [earned investigations-assisted by the Congolese T, Obenga (1973) and the Cameroonio,n Mveng (1972)-seek to give Africa the moral benefit of being the cradle of humankind and of having influenced th;~ history of ancient Egypt as well as Mediterra1.1ean ci.viHzations, But could these potentially mobilizing myths provide, as Diop hoped (1960c), the possibility of a new political crder in Africa? E, 111 fl '\V,vTv . ()UES1'IC)J\TS , . ..,, The Ambiguitie§ of an Ideokigical All:ernati.v,e Toute ma vie, politiquemerrt, je me suis fair de la bile. }'en induis que le seul Pere que j'ai connu (que je me suis donn~) a ete le Pere politique. Roland Barthes par Roland Barthes. In hi.s fore,.vord to Selected Letters of Edward Wilmat Blyden (1978) coilected by Hollis R. Lynch, L S. Senghor celebrates Blyden as the "foremost precu.rsor both of Negriiude and of the African Personality" (Lynch 1978:xv-xxii). The father of negritude thinks that a century before the emergence of modem African ideology, Blyden prcmoted its spirit. Fi.rst, because Blyden. treated "both the virtues of Negritude and and proper modes of illustrating these virtues: through scholarly studies, life styles a:rid cultural creaton." Second, because "through the stimulus of a 'revolution of mentalities'," Blyden tried "1:0 lead 1'-Jegro-Americans to rnlitivate what is 'authentically' theirs: their 'African Personality' ... and advocated already 'i:he :nethod which is ours today: to find one's roots in the values of Negritude, while remaining open to those of non-African civilizations." Third, because as a "true universal man," Blyden ";;Jready believed, as vve do today, that all progress in a civilization can only come from a mixing of cultures"" Lynch, author of a biography of Blyden, agrees with Senghor and writes that "the modern concept of Negritude . , . can find respectable historical roots in the writings of Blyden" (1967:252). He also stresses the influence of Blyden on such ideologues as the Nigeri,m Nnamdi Azikiwe and the Ghan.aian Kwame Nkrumah and states that "Blyden 'Nas rhe ideological father of the idea of '\Xfest African unity": "he inspired nationalism in the individual territories," and his "pan-1~egro ideology was undoubtedly the most important prD·· genitor of Pan-Afr.icariism" (1967:24.9-50). A native of the Danish island of SL Thomas, E. Y//. Blyden (1832-1912) settled In '\X~esAt frica i.n I 8 5 1 and rapid1y became one of the most careful / E W. Biyden's Legacy 99 students of African affairs. A permanent resident of Liberia and Sierra Leone, he saw the beginning of the scramble for Africa, studied the arrival of European settlas on the 1X!est Coast, and observed the progressive establishment of colonial n:ile, He was the author of several vt1orks, h is not my intention to present an exegetic interpreration of myden's work, 1:.or to offer a nevv understanding of his life and achievements, K am concerned 'With a practical question in che precise field of the history oif African ideologies: in ,what sense car we accept Senghor's and Lynch\; st8tements about Blyden as the precursor of aegritude and "Afric.m Personality"? Thus, I will not "interpret" Blydw's theses from the point of vievv of historical data nov, available, b111: instead will focus on their significance and limitations, and will v,hen necessary, situa~e them in their "i_deological atmosphere." I shall, therefore, describe the signs and symbols of Blyden's ideology as expressed by such texts as Vindication of the Negro Race ( I 8 5 7 ), Liberia's Offering (1862.), The Negro in Ancient History (1869), Liberia: Past, Present and Future (1869), Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race (1888), and Africa and the Africans (1903). I use the themes of Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race as an organizing frame, This book, a miscellaneous collection of various 1:exts-artides, speeches, reviews--is Blyden's major work (see Lynch, 1967:73--78). Quotations from his letters add subjectivity to some of Blyden's more formal theses. h1 this first section, I vviH present .Blyden's thesis on. colonization and his interpretation of the "Negro's condition"; in the next, I will shovv hlY.v he sees the African and defines his own political philosophy. My conduslon on his leg:1cy attempts a critical synthesis and stl'dies Blydlen's racial attitudes and "prophetism" and proposes 2. critical interpretatiori. of Sen.ghor's and Lynch's statements. The method used is simple. Blyden'~ work is not anaJyzed as sign or symbol of something else, but only in terms of its ovvn density and spiritual limits, as it reveals its o,;m irrediucibility and specificity. At the same time, because this work ws,s produced within a given historical period and a specific inteHectual dimate, I thought it valid to rewrite its "passion" in the manner of Foucault, as a simple discourse-object. Given Blyden's personal situation-a West Indian Black who, denied education in the United States, emigrated to Liberia (Blyden, L0:8; Lynch, 1967:73)-one can understand that his ideas concerning colonization express both racial and nationali:;tic positions aimed at achieving a particular type of social revolution, On April :w, 1860, he wrote to 'William Gladstone, then British Chancellor of the Exchequer about Liberia: "this little Republic, planted here in great weakness, is no doubt destined, in the providence of God, to revolutionize for good the whoie of that portion of Africa" (Blyden, LET:30). But i.n a letter written on June 9 of the same year to the Rev~ John L 'IX/ilson, Corresponding Secretary of the Board of Foreign l\11issions of the American Presbyterian Church, Blyden speaks of being "instrumental in doing anything towards establishing the respectability of my race," Significantly; he wis:1es that his efforts for the promotion of the "Alexander High 100 The Invendon of Africa School" in IVIonrovia wiH contribute 1:0 "a partial solution" to questions ab'.:lut the J',,iegro'csa pabilities: 'The great problem to be solved is v1hether black men, under favornble circu!'instances, can manage their own affairs ... wit1.-ie fficiency.' 'Will the efforts now put fo'"th in the Alex High School, if eificiem and successful, contribute to a partial solutioH of the problem? And, on the other hand, if those efforts fail, will the impression be deepened tha, the prcblern is insolvable [sic], anci W'iHth e gloom vmich has so long rested upon the race increase in density? H so, then let me be forever discarded by the black race, and let me be ccndernned by the white, if I strive not with all my powers, if! put not forth al~ my energies to contribute to so import,mt a solut1ion. (Blyden, LET:31) One might focus on this sign: an explicit need for over-compensation il:r:mdormed into a ~will-for-power. But this will for "the progress of the race" is l2,rgely determined by an apologetic objective. For, as Blyden put it at the end of his treatise on The Negro in Ancient History, "we believe that as descendants of Ham had share ... in the founding of cities and in the organization of go,rernment, so members of the san1e farnHy~ developed under differenc circumstances, vviH have an important part in the dosing of the great d,:ama" (NAH:28). In this regard, he denies to whites any positive cuh:ural presence in Africa and frequently insists on the fact that only black peoples can transform the continent. Yet he seriously advocates colonization a5 one of the possible means of metamorphosis. Blyden's understanding of the process of Africa's opening up to a white presence is ambiguous: The modem desire for more accurate know-ledge of Afoica is not a mere senti1nent; it is the philanthropic impulse to lift up the millions of that continent to their proper position among the intellectual and moral forces of the world; but it is also che commercial desire to open that vast country to the enterprises of trade. (Blyden, CINR, 9 5) There remains the "civilizing mission." He even refers to the first years of slavery as being positive: "The slave trade was regarded as 2 great means of oivilizing the blacks-a kind of missionarl institution." Africans were at that time "not only indoctrinated into the principles of Christianity, but they were taught the arts and sciences." "The relation of the European to the African in those unsophisticated times, was that of guardism and protege" (LPPF:7-8). Despite the fact that Blyden certainly had knowledge of Belgian atrocities in the Congo, his stated opinion of King Leopold's enterprise in Africa 'Nas that "everyone has confidence in the philanthropic aims and the practical and commercial eHorts of the King of Belgians in the arduous and expensive enterprise he has undertaken in the Congo" (Lynch, 1967:208). In his Africa and Africans, written in 1903, he cdebrated Leopold and the Belgians as "providential" agents for the regeneration of the continent and added that, "retribution for their misdeed:; vvill come from God" (Blyden, AA: 4 5; \ E, 1770B lyden's Legacy IOI Lynch, 1967:2.09). But the same yea::, in a letter to John Holt, he was quilbe angry about "the horrible proceedings in the Congo," Identif1ing Leopold with a mythical 2.nd monstrous Pharaoh, he noted that the lf social cultures and progress. This practice of 2,rguing by means of sociological corucepts, or, as he defines it, "the science of Race" (CINR:94), leads hirn to "the poetry" of politics: It is the feeling of race-the aspiration after the development on its own line oif the type of humanit)' to which we belong. Italians and Germans long yearned after such development. The Slavonic tribes are feelig after it, Now, nothing tends more to discourage these feelings and check these aspirations, than the idea rhat the people with vvhorn we are connected, and after whose improvement we sigh, have never had a past, or only an ignoble past-antecedents w-hich vvere 'blank and hopeless,' to be ignored and forgotten. (CIN'R:197) Blyden tends to avoid both the easy antislavery propaganda, with its myths about the "noble savage," and also the technical debates 011 the hierarchy of races. R,tther than defining the African as a "special" counterpart of the Europe,m-a "noble savage" or a "beastly primitive"-Blyden used his literary background i.:o describe the African as a victim of a European ethnocentrism. For instance, he considered contempt of Africa11s and Neg"oes to be a modem invention. He referred to Homer's and Herodotus's descriptions of blacks, insisied on the frequency of kalos kagathos (handsome and good) Ethiopian in classical literature, and discussed the aesthetic value of the color black: in the Bible (NAB: L,j; see also Bomgeois, 1971; kv1veng, r972). h1 Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race, he affirmed that "In Greek and Latin languages and their literature, there is not, as far as I know, a sentence, a word, or a syllable disparaging to the Negro" (CINR:84). Commenting on a poem atributed to Virgil and quoting Homer's celebration of the :Negro Eurybates at the siege of Troy, he states that "the disparagement began with European travellers, partly 'from a desire to be unfair' or 'from preconceived notions of the ]\Tegro,' 'and partly, also, on the principle that i.t is easier to pull down than to build up'" (CINR:263), These explanations do not constitute a convincing historical description. Yet, in very genernl terms, they situate the ideological justifications used first by travders and then by exp1orers and missionaries to establish a new order in the "dark continent" (see Arendt, 1968:87). This meant opening Africa to trade, European education, and Christianity, and thus setting up and enforcing a psychological domination: E. WI. B!yden's Legacy III In all EngHsl:Mpeaking countries the mind of the intelligent Negro child revolts against the descriptions given in elementary books-geographies, travels, histories-of the Negrn; but, though he experiences an instinctive revulsion from the~e caricatures and misrepresentations, he is obliged to continue, as he grows in years, to study such pemiicious teachings. After leaving school he finds the same things in newspapers, in reviev.1si,n r,ovels, in quasi-scientific works; and after a while-saepe cadendo--they begin to seem to him the proper things to say and to feel about his race. (BlydeG, CINR:76) Thinking of the condition of Black Americans in particular, Blyden generalized his analysis: Those who have lived in civilized communities, where there are different races, know the disparaging views which are entertained of the blacks by their neighbours-and often, alas! by themselves. The standard of all physical and intellectual excellencies in the present civilization being the white complexion, whatever deviates from that favoured colour is proportionally depreciated, until the black, which is the opposite, becomes not only the most unpopular but the most unprofitable colour. (CINR:77) Blyden dealt courageously with this difficult aspect of psychological dependence, He thought that the Negro was weak because he accepted the image imposed on him and that this complex of dependence could account for the "hesitancy," the "modesty growing out of a sense of inferiority" found in the Black Arcr1.ericampu pil (CINR:q .8), as well as for the self-depreciation seen in the adult, "It is painful in America to see the efforts which are made by Negroes to secure outward conformi!'J to the appearance of the dominant race" (CINR:77), As for the Negro in general, Blyden pointed out that derogatory perspec· tives provide the inteUectual framework of this psychological waro An opposition of colors, black versus white, becomes the paranmumt symbol of the distance in quality and virtue beitween Europeans and i\fricans, and justifies the white man's duty toward "despised races" (CINR:138). But this dut'y seems a myth and its 'Norks will not last: Victor Hugo exhorts ":he European nations to 'occupy this land offered to them by God.' He has forgotten the prudent advice of Caesar to the ancestors of those nations against i1wading Africa. The Europeans can hold the domain 'offered to them' by only a precarious tenure. (ClNR:145-46) Rejecting the theme of the barbarous Negro, Blyden focused on the co:1nec1:ion between degener2.tion and Westernization. ln his view, not aH European accomplishments are splendid and useful. On the contrary, "things which have been of great advantage to Europe m2y work ruin to us; and there is often such a striking resemblance, or such a close connection between the hurtful and the beneficial that we are not always able to discriminate" I Lt The Invention of Africa (CKNR:79). Furtherrnore, he observed that ithe most visible consequence for the Kingciom of Congo, 1JVestemized and Christianized under Portuguese influence during the seventeenth cent1.uy, was its disappearance ( CINR: I 5 9 ). One could even think that Blyden-although he was a Christian minister- did not believe in conversion, lnsofar as it is an expression of \1Vestemization: "Pagans of discernment know that the black man among them who 'calls himself a Christian and dresses himself in dothes' adheres to Et1ropean habits an.cl customs with a reserved povver of disengagement" (CINR: 5 9 ). He strongly ridiculed the confusion of sodornltural customs and Christian values andl pessimistically noted that "the Gospel has failed to have free course in this land" (LET: I I 5 ). However, he believed that the "inconsistencies of Christians" (LET:99) might account for this relative failure, In actuality, what he rejected was the "thin varnish of European civilization" that a young and inexperienced missionar1 propagates. "With the earnest vigour and sanguine temper which belong to youth he preaches a crusade against the harmless customs and prejudices of the people-superseding many customs and habits necessary and useful in the climate 2.nd for the people by practices which, however useful they might be in Europe, become, when introduced indiscriminately into Africa, artificial, ineffective and absurd" (CINR:64), Hmvever, Blyden seems to believe that the confusing of religious values and cultural customs is not an accident: "The Anglo-Saxon mind and the African mind trained under Anglo-Saxon influence, seem to be intolerant of all customs and practices which do not conform to the standard of European tastes and habits" (LET: I 14.). This instance of cultural misunderstanding is neither extraordinary nor unusuaL Of at least equal significance is the supposed African response to Europeans and their culture, There are those of other races vvho also sneer and scorn and 'despise! Some of the proceedings of Baker and Stanley in Africa must frequently have impressed the natives with the feeling that those energetic travellers can1e from much 'darker continents' than any of their unsophisticated imaginations had ever before suggested to them, (Cil',TR:138-9) Mungo Park recorded his impressions as follows: Although the Negro(;s, in general, have a great idea of the wealth and power of Europeans, I am afraid that the Mohammedan converts among them think but very little of our superior attainments in religious knowledge ... The poor Africans, whom we affect to consider as barbarians, look upon us, I fear, as tittle better than a r:?.ce of formidable but ignorant Heathen. (Cil'-IR:343) For Blyden, these incongruities revealed the general tone of a distorted contact as it existed under slavery and colonial imperialism. Moreover, to the degree that the European presence and self-proclaimed political supremacy affect the African's culture and confidence (LO: 57), Blyden felt it necessary to overemphasize certain ideological issues w-hich would eventually foster the African's silent resistance and would bring about a new climate of ideas, The E. VV. Blyden's Legacy logic of this comm.itment led Blyden to formulate strong intellectual criticisms of \Ylestem ideology, principally through a critical evaluation of the European tradition, a new interpretation of history, and, finally, a positive evaluation of African oral tradition. Blyden's criticism of the European tradition is based on a relativist philosophy of cultures (AA:60). He believed that even though, in religious terms, the concept of humankind is the same throughout the world, "the native capacities of mankind differ, and their work and destiny differ, so that the road by which one man may attain to the highest efficiency, is not that which would conduce to the success of another" (AA:5-8; CH•TR:83). Fanciful excursions in the field of comparative history provided some comparisons to support his relativism. The ancestors of these people [Africans] understood the use of the cottonplant, and the manufacture of cotton, when Julius Caesar found the Britons clothing themselves in the skins of wild beasts. Visitors to the British Museum may see, in the Egyptian department, doth of the very same material and texture wrapped around the mummies. This cloth vvas made by those who understood the lost art of embalming, but who, when they retired by successive revolutions, into the interior ... lost that valuable art, but never forgot the manufacture of the doth used in the process, (CINR: 196) This is only one of many fragile comparisons. Hi.s comments on Leo Africanus's reports about the kingdom of Mali ( CINR: r 9 5 ), Egyptian physical characteristics (NAH: r o ), Ethiopian psychology (NAH: 2 5-26), and destiny (CINR: I 52-3 ), or the civilitzadon of the "Mohammedans of Negritia" (CINR: 300) make explicit and uphold his ideas on the diversity of historical processes, This premise allowed him to state that: The special road which has led to the success and elevation of the Anglo-Saxon is not that which would lead to the success and elevation of the Negro, though we shall resort to the same means of general culture which has enabled the Anglo-Saxon to find out for himself the way in which he ought to go. (CINR:83) This critical position, in fact, also required a new understanding of history. Since the kind of political and cultural domination that was taking place in Africa served the particular historical perspective on which it was based and was, in return, justified by its own success, Blyden chose to revise the concept of history altogether. Referring to E Harrison's classification, vvhich distinguished "six leading epochs in the history of civilization" (Theocratic Society, Greek Age, Roman Period, Medieval Civilization, Modem Age, and the Age since the French Revolution), Blyden proposed to exclude the study of the last two ages from the African curriculum. His reasons were quite simple. He observed that it was during these periods, especially the last, that "the trans-Adantic slave The lnvention of Afri:::a trade arose, and those the•ories--theological, social, ;1n:d political-were invented for the degradation and proscription of the Negro." On the other hand, he considered the first periods, particularly the Greek, the Itiornan, an::l the lvkdieval to be exemplary: "There has been no period of hist01y more fuU of suggestive en,ergy, both physical and intellectual, than those epochs .. , .l\To modem writers will ever influence the destiny of the race to the sarne extent that the Greeks and Romans have done" (CINR:82), Thus a philosophical principle of cultural relativism accompanied an ideological rejection of a part of European history ;;ind permitted Blyden to justify his daim for authenticity, and, therefore, the relevance of the African past and its proper i:radition. Following Volney (NAH: 5) and Hartmann, he had no doubts about "the strictly Africar:: extraction" of the pharaonic civilization (CINR: I 54n). But it w2,s through an evaluation of Africa's oral traditions th2.t he savv the basis for inspiration: Now, if we ;ire to make an independent nation-a strong nation--we must listen to che songs of our unsophisticated brethren as they sing of their history, as they tell of their tr:c,,ditions, of the wonderful and mysteriot 1s events of their tribal or national life, of the achievements of what we call their superstitions. (CINR:91) in sum, -what Blyden put forward is a general criticism of \XTestern ideology, not because it was wrong, but because it seemed to him irrelevant for African authenticity. This criticism, however, arose as a negation, and to some degree as a consequence, 0£ the most intolerant "race-,thinking" interpretations. Thus, it is a warping reworking of the most negative theories of the century. In a long letter to the British traveler Mary Kingsley in 1900, Blyden could 2cg:ee with her: "'The Negro rnust have ~• summit to himself'-a remark vvhi.ch is not the result, as has been alleged by some, of prejlidice to the African, nor, as it has been hdd by others, af latitudenarian indifference to religious truth~" (LET:461). Playing upon the ambiguous significance oJt Swedenborg's expression that the African is a celestial man, he could also, in a most rdativist fashion, conclude that "such a man among terrestrials m_ust have a separate place-not a hole into which some would thrust him, nor a dead flat where others would fix him, but a summit." Therefore, "for obvious reaso1:1s the conventional morality of Europe cannot be the conventional morality of Africa, so far as social or doraestic mauers are concerned" (LET:46I). Three major considerationf; were central to Blyden's political philosophy: the basic organized community under Muslim leadership, the concept of the African nation, and, finally, the idea of the unity of the continent. The basic Isfamk comnmnit1; appears to be his model of political organization. "There are no caste distinctions among them" nor "tribal barriers" (CINR:175) nor racial prejud.ices (CINR:15-17); "slavery and the slavetrade are laudable, provided the slaves are KaHirs," but the "slave -who erabraces Islam is free, and no office is closed against him on account of his E. VV. Blyden's Legacy servile blood" (ONR:176). Did Blyden approve of this institutional slavery? h is not dear. One could perhaps argue that he 'Was just presenting one case. 1w'e must keep in mind thal: throughout his publications he opposed slavery (e.g., L0:67-91; L0:153-67). At any rate, -what he admired in the system was that for Muslims the social relations of production are not determined by racial factors but by their faith: "'Paradise is under the show of swords,' is one of their stimulating proverbs" (CINR:9). "They gather under the beams of the Crescent not only for religious, but for patriotic reasons; till they are only swayed with one idez, but act as one individual. The faith becomes a part of their nationality, and is entwined with their affections" ( CINR: 2 3 r ), The dynamism of these Muslim communities, their subtle and intelligent ways of proselytizing, and thei.r trade assured Islam a brilliant future in Africa. "AH careful and candid observers agree that the influence of Islam in Central and West Africa has been, upon the whole, of a mos,~ salutary character. As an eliminatory and subversive agency, it has displaced or unsettled nothing as good as itself" (CINR:174). None of the Nigritian tribes have ever abdicated their race individuality or parted with their idiosyncrasies in embracing the faith of Islam. But, whenever and wherever it has been necessary, great Negro warriors have risen from the ranks of Islam, and, inspired by the teachings of .:he new faith ... have driven them, if at anytime they affected superiorit'/ based upon race, from their artificial ascendancy. (CINR:122) According to Blyden, Islam is politically an excellent means of promoting an African consciousness and of organiziing communities. Unfortunatdy, though the ideological assumptions can be accepted in principle, the historical facts badly contradict Blyden's belief in the positive capabilities of Islam. Throughout the nineteemh centur1 in Central Africa, Islamk factions represented an objective evil and practiced a shameful slave-trade. And here, again, we face an unbelievable inconsistency in Blyden's thought: his naive admiration for Islam led him. to accept the enslavement of non-.!vfoslim peoples! The concept of the African nation is perhaps the most puzzling, but also the most original one, in Blyden's writings. It impli.es the classkal conception of "democracy" (LPPF::i:6) but with a special focus on the rejection of racial distinction, and at the same time, the paradoxlcal daim for the retention of racial individuality. In actuality, as a m::m of his time, Blyden used the romantic premises, which in the nineteenth century allowed some European theorists to rediscover their historical roots and then celebrate the authenticity of their own culture and civilization, in terms of their identity with their origins. The most conspicuous t<..xample of this process is the debate which took place among German scholars on the "Inda-European" or "Inda-Germanic" cultme, in which a most remarkable confusion existed about the notions of "race," "language," "tradition," and "history" (see, e.g., Arendt, 1968:45-64). Nevertheless, European nationalisms arose, m II6 The In'!ention of Africa part, from theoretical combinations of these cornplex and comroversid no-tions and accounted for what Blyden called "the period of rnce organizacion and race consolidation" (CINR: I 22). Like his European counterparts, Blyden did not doubt th~11a: racial phenomenon must be the b2sis o:f nationalism and the foundation of the Nation: On this q'iestion of race, no argument is necessa.cy in discussing the methods or course d procedure for the }'reservation of r2.ce int•egrity, and for the development of race efficiency, but no argument is needed as to the necessity of such preservation and development. ff a man does not feel it-if it does not rise up with spcr;taneous and inspiring power in his heart-then he has neither part ocr lot in it. (CINR:122-23) Thus, r,;taining the concept of racial individuality became the cornerstone in the construction of a nation. ParadoxicaHy, Blyden wrote that he did 11ot consider Haiti and Liberia, the tv,o major black nations, 2,s possible models for the African nation, because "there is a perpetual struggle between the very few who are aiming w forward the interests of the many, :md the profanum vulgus, largely in majorit'f'' (CINR:273). Moreover, as he grew· older, Blyden accepted the partition of Africa by European powers (see Lynch in LET:409), collaborated with them (LET:502), and in 1909, ·worked very hard for the "reconstructing [of] Liberia by tbe Uni.Led States"; and indei::d for a process of administrative "coionizationo" Let the Rep11blic .retain her Executive, Legislative and Judicial Departments. But let America take the Republic under her 'Protection' for the time being. Let the British officers, as they are doing now supervise the Customs and Treasury Departments. Let the French manage the Froncier Force under Liberian financial respo::isfoiliry, Let America 3ppoint a High Commissioner for Liberia-an experienced Southern man, if possible, surround him with the necessary white American officials to help. Abolish the Am::rican Legation at .Monrovia or put a 7vhite man at the head. The High -Commissioner shot1Ed review the Executive, Legislative and Judicial decisions before they are s2nctioned. (LET:496) How-ever, it is in his descriptions of Liberia and Sierra Leone that heof fered hits dearest view 0£ an African nation, which inust be independent, liberal, and self-reliant but must trade with other foreign countries, a "good democrncy" in which racial self-elevation would be 1:he guiding principle. Blyden·'s Pan-Africanism is a sort of prophetisrn .. I-Ie envisioned, first, a collaboration and 2, fusion of African Christianity and the sonquering force of Islam: -,\X!herteh e light from the Cross ceases to stream upon the gloom, there the beams of the Cres-::ent will give illumination; and, as the glorious orb of ChriGtianity rises, the tv,ilight of Mam will be lost in the greater light of the Sun of Righteousness. Then Isaac and Ishmael will be m!ited. (CINR:233) E. W. Blyden's Legacy II7 Second, he emphasized the cultural unity that Islam represents. It has placed African peoples "under the same inspiration" (CINR:229), giving them, by means of the same "language, letters, and books" (CINR:229), both a political unity and a cultural community (CINR:6). Finally, Africa will unite when it pays due attention to its experiences with Europe and America. He thus maintained the thesis that "the political history of the United States is the history of the Negro. The commercial and agricultural history of nearly the whole of America is the history of the Negro" (CINR:119; LET:476- 77). In sum, there would be unity and growth in Africa if black peoples all over the world would reflect upon their own condition. Blyden, the ideologue, became a visionary: In visions of the future, I behold those beautiful hills-the banks of those charming streams, the verdant plains and flowery fields . . . I see them all taken possession of by the returning exiles from the West, trained for the work of re-building waste places under severe discipline and hard bondage. I see, too, their brethren hastening to welcome them from the slopes of the Niger, and from its lovely valleys ... Mohammedans and Pagans, chiefs and people, all coming to catch something of the inspiration the exiles have brought-to share ... and to march back ... towards the sunrise for the regeneration of a continent. (CINR:129) A modern cultural and political organization would be achieved with the help of Americans of African descent. The interpenetration of religious and political "nationalisms" expresses in Blyden's thought what we must call a policy of racial authenticity, oriented towards a cultural and political transformation of the continent. The instrumental role that he accorded Black Americans and West Indians by selecting them as "colonists" indicates his belief in "racial identity" and illustrates his peculiar philosophy about the salvation of Africa. The restoration of the Negro to the land of his fathers will be the restoration of a race to its original integrity, to itself; and working by itself, for itself and from itself, it will discover the methods of its own development, and they will not be the same as the Anglo-Saxon methods. (CINR:IIo) Black people from America and West Indies have "served" and "suffered," and Blyden did not hesitate to compare them to the Hebrews (CINR:120). The possibility of their return to Africa becomes the hope for the promised land. Blyden has been called the founder of African nationalism and PanAfricanism. Surely he is, insofar as he described the burden of dependence and the drawbacks of exploitation. He put forward "theses" for liberation, insistiQ.g on the necessity of both the indigenization of Christianity and the support of Islam. Despite its romanticism and inconsistencies, Blyden's The Invention of PJrica political vision is probably c:he first proposal by a black m;;m to elaborate the benefits of an independeat, m.odem political structure for the continent, "ll3Jack Persm1ality" as Co:mnmn Locm Acccrding to Biydei:, the "Negro" that the ·w/es\:d eals with in its literature as well as in its imperial enterprise is just a myth (Blyden, LO: 52-54; 67- 68 ). The 1JVest has produced this myth and maintains it by projecting it as a standard image, Missionaries, travelers, and colonial settlers are equally wrong in the v-1ayth ey portray the African personality: The Negro of the ordinal:y traveller or mis5ionary-and perhaps, of two-thirds of the Christian world-is a purely fictitious being, constructed out of the traditions of slave-traders and slave-holders, who ha·,e circulated all sorts d absurd stories, and also out of prejudices inherited from ancestors, who were taught to regard the Negro as a legitimate object of traffic (CINR: 5 8) 1\/Iore generally, Blyden saw this false image as both the product and the consequence of a long process v;foch accompanied the European exploration of the world from the fifteenth century on, A prevailing ethnocentrism and a lack of sincere curiosity produced a totally absurd framework, in which African cultures and peoples constituted merely an inversion of European traditions and human types. This premise was used to justiiJ "the indictment agai!lst a whole race" (NAH:2 7). For example, Sir Samuel Baker states: "\"Vithout foreign assistance, the Negro a thousand years hence will be no better than the Negro of today,, as the r,Jegro of today is in no superior position to that of his ancestors some thousand years ago" (C!NR:269), Blyden attacked this ideological positon, first by indicating the weakness of its vitW, stemming from an erroneous deduction; and then by criticizing the asmmption that the Negro could be compiet,::ly integrated into "\:Vestern culture. Concerning the deduction, he vvrote that the major mistake lies in a theoretical misinterpretation of the racial phenomenon and its cultural manifestations: There is no absolute or essential superiority on the one side, nor absolute or essential inferiority on the other si,de. It is a question of diifference of endov\T·· memt and difference of destiny, No amount of training or culture wiU :nake the Negro a European; on the other hand, no fa.ck of training or deficiency of cuh:ure will make the European a Negro. The two races are not moving in the same groove with an immeasurable distance between them, but on parallel lines. They will never meet in rhe plane of their activities so as to coincide in capacity or performance. They are not identical, as some think, but unequal; they are distinct but equal. (CINR:22-7; ,ny emphasis) The difficulty of thi3 position lies in the complexity oc the con;:ept of race, and the various and extended connotations given to it by theorists and E. W. Blyden's Legacy II9 ideologi.sts. One could ana!yze the relationship between Blyden's thesis and the racial theories of his time (see, e.g., fanoudh-Siefor, 1968; Hanunond andJablm1v, 1977; Hoffmann, 1973; Jordan, 1968; Lyons, 1975). Since these theories are, generally speaking, mixtures of. poor philosophy, scientific speculations, and heavy ethnocentrism, it is more pertinent to look at the problem in a different ·way and to relate Blyden to rhe founders of anthropology. First of all, there is a striking similarity between Blyden's conception anci that of some of the eightee.i1th. .c entury anthropologists. His understanding of "anthropology," the study of "practical features" of "a system," and their influence on the natural man (CINR:232.), seems to echo Rousseau. As H. R. Lynch rightly notes: "Blyden's 'natural African man' is strikingly similar to Rousseau's 'noble savage' living in a 'perfect state of nature'-a state which they both claimed was the necessary prerequisite for the development of the spiritual resources of the mankind" (Lynch, 1967=62). Blyden's theory of race makes exceHent sense when it is related to Arthur de Gobineau's Essai sur l'inegalite des races humaines (1853) and other widespread racial conceptions. For instance, Voltaire, seeking a hierarchy of races in both his Traite de metaphysique (1734) and Essai sur les moeurs, affirmed that black peoples constitute a completely distinct brand of humankind. In Voltaire's anthropology, thi.s distinction implied and explained the Negro's inferiority (see Duchet, 1971:281-321), !n contrast, Buffon, a sdentist, presented ia his ]'l[atural History (1749) the principle of the distinctiveness of all human beings. To him, even "the most animal-like of human beings" does not resemble "the most hmnan-like of animals." He cc1.lledt his principle an organizztional identity, He also claimed 11:oh ave evidence of racial distinctions, acknowledgbg within every race the possible existence of "human varieties" dependent upon environment and climate (See Duchet, 1971:229-80). Believing in the distinctiveness of races, Blyden equated "purity" of race and "purity" of personality or blood. This accounts for his "racist" position about mulattoes. He wrote, for example, against "the introduction on a very large scale of the blood of the oppressors among their victims" (LET:488), denied even the possibility of a union between "the pure Negroes and! mulattoes" (LET: 3 88), and, in a most questionable manner, disparaged. "l'.Jegroes v?ho are as white as some white men" (LET: 3 8 8 ). His thesis requiring the rejection of mulattoes from the "race" and from the African experience was also politirnlly motivated: "H this difference between the Negro and the mulatto is understood hereafter, it 'NiH much simplify the Negro problem, and the race will be called upon to bear i.ts own si:ns only, and not the sins also of a 'mixed multitude'" (in Lynch, 1967:59). Blyden seems to agree also with the principle of human variety within the race but added to it the fact of ethnic difference and social influence: The cruel accidems of slavery and the slave-trnde drove all Africans together, and no discrimination vvas made in ,he shambles between the Foulah and the Timneh, the 11.dandingo and the IVIendi, the Ashan!ee and the Fantee, the Eboe I1.0 The Invention of Africa and the Gongo-berween the descendams of Nobles and the offsprings of sbves, between kings and their subjects--aH were placed on the same level, aU oc black skin and 'Noolly hair were 'niggers,' ch,rcteh ... And when, by any cotuse of events, these people 2.ttempt to exercise independent government, they st2,rt in the eyes of the world as Africans, without the fact being taken into consideration that they belong to tribes 2.nd fainilie~ differing wideiy in degrees of intelligence and capacity, in original bent and S'.lsceptibiiity. (CINR:274) The last sen~ence implies the concept of variety by establishing a relationship between "intelHgence" or "capacity" ar:d ethnic groups. This is a dangerous hypothesis, which during the last t7vo centuries has been co-opted to legitimate every rac:s~n and has supported the foundation of the controversial science of racial differences. In Blyden's ideological perspective, this concept i.s a powerful claim for regional identity: Africans are not identical, their social organizatior:s are not equal, nor necessarily similar, and, finally, their traditions do not merely reflect each other and are not the same. Nevertheless, Blyden claimed a general distinctiveness of Africa and her people and defined it by listing some particular characteristics of the continent and its inhabitants in a dearly Rousseauist and ethaocentrist vvay. Africa "has been called the cradle of civilization, and so it is," Thinking of the Egyptian past, Blyden wrote: "The germs of all sciences and of the tvm great religions nml\/ professed by the most enlightened races were £01,tered in Africa" (CINR:II6; :NAH:5--9). In his view, it was a bi:illiant world, a continent of "contentmem and happine&s" vvhere people feared and loved God and showed ~·emarkabie hospitality (L0:82). lf the belie£ in a Common Creator and Father of mankind is illustrnted in the bearing we mainta.in towards our neighbour, if our faith is seen in our v,orks, if we prove that we love God, whorn we have not seen, by loving our neighbour whom we have seen, by respecting his rights, even though he 1112:y 1-::obt elong to our clan, tribe, or race, then I must s.ay, and it will not be generally disputed, that more proofs are fun1ished 2111ongth e natives of interior Africa of their belief in the common Fatherhood of a personal God by their hospitable and considerate treatment of foreignecs and strnngers than are to be _seen in rriany a civilized aed Christian community. (CINR:n5) To illustrate his statement on African religiosity, Blyden recalled Ho,mer's and Herodotuds eulogies of the "blameless Black peoples" CNAH: rn ). Concerning ho:,pirality, besides some ethnographic analyses on Mandingo customs ( CINR: I 8 5) and Ivfongo Park's experience in the vicinity of Sego (CINR::w6), he brought in explorers' testimoflies, and among them, the amazing "long sojourn of Livingstone in that Lmd , .. wi-d1out money to pay his way, .. , another proof of the excellent qualities of the peopies" ( 1:=II:.{[2I, .I :5 ).. 1\vo other characteristics of Africans, according to Blyden, are their love of music ((::INR:276) and their "teachableness" (CINR:163). He focused on E. W. Blyden's Legacy 121 this last capability because of its potential for Africa's future. It seemed to him all the more important since he was convinced of a general state of "degeneration," at least among "Pagans." But "Moslems," generally, constitute. an exception: "Wherever the Moslem is found on this coast ... he looks upon himself as a separate and distinct being from his Pagan neighbour, and immeasurably his superior in intellectual and moral respects" (CINR:175). A century has made no change for better. Mr. Joseph Thompson [who) visited the Nigritian countries last year [says]: There is absolutely not a single place where the natives are left to their own free will, in which there is the slightest evidence of a desire for better things. The worst vices and diseases of Europe have found a congenial soil, and the taste for spirits has risen out of all proportion to their desire for clothes. (CINR:342) Thus, general degeneration exists mainly due to intemperance (CINR:67), the climatic influences (CINR:54), and the European presence (CINR:46- 47; LET:399-400). In order to stop this deadly process, Blyden proposed a course of action consisting of three principal methods for the African's conversion, all of them based on the capacity for learning. First, there was to be an emphasis on "our past" and the objectivity of reality. For as Blyden remarked, "our teachers have of necessity been Europeans, and they have taught us books too much, and things too little." Consequently, "the notion, still common among Negroes ... is that the most important part of knowledge consists in knowing what other menforeigners- have said about things, and even about Africa and about themselves. They aspire to be familiar, not with what really is, but with what is printed" (CINR:220). In daily existence the expression of this failure to distinguish between "reality" and subjective "interpretation" leads Africans into absurd situations. The songs that live in our ears and are often on our lips are the songs which we heard sung by those who shouted while we groaned and lamented. They sang of their history, which was the history of our degradation. They recited their triumphs, which contained the records of our humiliation. To our great misfortune, we learned their prejudices and their passions, and thought we had their aspirations and their power. (CINR:91) According to Blyden, it is likely that this cultural trend will simply lead to the Negro's destruction. One means of conversion would be the development of "black consciousness," since it is clear that "in spite of all, the "Negro race" has its part to play still-a distinct part-in the history of humanity, and the continent of Africa will be the principal scene of its activity" (CINR:276). Yet he claims that we must place the Western perception of "us" and of "our past" in perspective and look for "what we are," live it and write it according to "our own" experience. 122 The Invention cf Africa We have neglected to study matters at home because we ·were trained in books wTitten by foreigners, and for a foreign race, not for us-or for us only so far as ir1-the general characteristics of humanit'j we resemble that race , .. There-· fore, we turned our backs upon our breathren of the interior as those from vrhom vve could learn nothing to elevate, to enlighten, or to refine . , . We have had history written for us, and ',Ve hmre endeavoured to act up to it; where as, the true c;rder is, that histo1y should be first acted, then ·written. (CINR:221; my emphasis) In other words, Africans have to create their own schemes for understanding and mastering social and historical data, "especially in this large and interesting country of theirs, 2.bout which the truth is yet to be found out-people and systems about which correct ideas are to be formed" (CUs.JR:220--u). 'What Blyden refers to is, li suspect, the necessity to implement an African social interpretation, which should be undertaken as an African responsibility, since, as he expressed it in his address at the inauguration of Liberia College, "\'ve have no pleasing antecedents-nothing in the past to inspire us ... Ail our agreeable associations are connected with the future. Let us then strive to achieve a glorious future" (LO: I 20 ). On a second level, Blyden struggled against the theme of mimicry of social behavior: "Fascinated by the present, [the :t'Jegro] harasses himself with the ever-recurring and ever-unsatisfying and unsatisfactory i:ask of im.itating imitators" (CKNR: 147). As a sign of psychological domination, imitation of the white man or the secret desire to become white expresses a dependence. 1n any case, research and discussion about this must take place in the determination of African culture and proposals for its _foture ( CliNR: 277--7 8 ). In addition, new and vigorous canons should be initiated immediately for young Blacks. The aim would be "to assist their povver of forgetfulness-an achievement of extreme difficulty" (CINR:79) by increasing "the amount of purely disciplinary agencies" and reducing "to its minimum the amolilnt of dic.tracting influences" (CINR:80). The aim of these canons vvould also be "to study the causes of Negro inefficiency in civilized lands; and, so far as it has resulted from the training they have received, to endeavour to avoid what we conceive to be the sinister elements in that training" (CINR:80), Emphasizing the special nature of the Liberian experience, he insisted on the fact that "no country in the world needs n10re than Liberia to have mind properly directed" (lD:98). First, because the country is "isolated from the civilized world, and surrounded by a benighted people." Second, the e:x:perience itself seems exceptional for it means "establishing and maintaining a popular government with a population, for the most part, of emancipated slaves" (L0:98). Referring to the first settlers, he insists on the necessity of "a practical education" (LO: 101). This project leads directly to the third major step: a new policy for formal education, ,Nhich ultimately would help the transformation of the continent. Using his ov,m experience as a professional, he proposed very precise outlines for a program, Above all, he put forward thls major thesis: "Lord Bacon says E. 'JV. Blyden's Legacy that 'reading makes a full man'; but the indiscriminate reading by the J',Jegro of European literature has made him, in many instances, too full, or has rather destroyed his balance" (CINR:81). From this position it is easier to understand the complementarity between his "classical perspective" and his "nationalist outlook" with respect to the curriculum. Kn addition to the critical presentation of history from an African point of view, he insisted on the study of classics-the Greek and Latin 'languages and their H:teraturesmathematics, and the Bible. The study of classi,ss----"the key to a thorough knowledge of all the languages of the enlightened part of mankind" (LO: r 08 )--,Nas necessary for tvvo main reasons. First, "what is gained by the study of the ancient languages is that strengthening and disciplining of the mind which enables the student in after life to lay hold of, and, vvi.th comparatively fade difficulty, to master any business to which he may turn his attention" (CINR:87). Second "the study of the Classics also lays the foundation for the successful pursuit of scientific knowledge. It so stimulates the mind that it arouses the student's interest in all problems of science" (C!NR:87; LO:no). (Let us note that these are the two main reasons Senghor put forward some ninety years later to promote the teaching of Greek, Latin, and classical literature in Senegal.) Blyden also advocated the study of physics, and mathemati.cs (LO: 100), because "as instmments of culture, they are everyw·here applicable" (CJNR:87). Finally, the study of the Bible is essential. Hmvever, it must be ,1 Bible "vlithout note or comment," since "the teachings of Christianity are of 1..miversal application . , . and the g:ceat truths of the Sermon on the fear of God; and this sentiment-which is the condition ot all other progressit is not only diffusing, but transmitting to posterity. This is the element which has given stability and upward impulse to the social and political forces of advanced countries; and it wiH have the same effect in the dark corners of this continent. (ONR:332) Blyden wrote elsewhere that Arabic, the language of Islam, is in Africa a good preparation for Christianity (CINR:187) and an important means for an 2u.tonomou.s and regional policy of auto-regeneration (LET: r 34-3 8 ). He firmly believed that Islam could have an excellent fotu.re throughout the continent. And as far as African interests are concerned, Blyden had faith in the practical superiority of Islam over Christianity: Mohammedanism, in Africa, has left the native master of himself and of his home; but wherever Christianity has been able to establish itself, with the exception of Liberia, foreigners have taken possession of the countri;, and, in some places, rule the natives with oppressive rigour. (CINR:309) This does not imply that Blyden could not or did not want to envisage the possibility of an African Christianity. He was a Christian Elinister, but refused to forget that he vvas black (see, e.g., LET:462). From his other views, one can see that he was bound to be skeptical about European Christianity and its processes of evangeli.zation: "There is no evidence that Christianity, or, rather professing Christians [ ... ] would have been less unscrupulous in their dealings with natives or Africa, than they have been with the natives of America, of Australia, of Nev.r Zealand" (CXNR:309). His position must be understood against the background of racism and its consequences, which iliuminates his reasons for stressing the generaHy negative influence of Christianity on Black people and "the innumerable woes which have attended the African race for the last three hundred years in Christian lands" (CINR:27). As he expressed it in his letter to N[ary Kingsley in 1900: "Very few among races alien to the European believe in the genuineness of the Christianity of the white man. For neither in the teaching nor the practice of the lay white man do they see manifested, as a rule, anything of the spirit of Christianity" (LET:462). Although he rejoiced in the apparent failure of Roman Catholicism in Liberi2. (LET:388), he seemed to admire this church, 1111hicihn his opinion presented remarkable characteristics: It is "an uncompromising front in the warfare against infidelity in all its forms" and "has alwa-ys been and is now a protesting power ... against those attacks upon constituted authority." Further, it is set "against the freeness and facility of divorce," "respects the integrity of the family," and "respects races." Finally, it holds to those words of St. Paul that dedare that 'God hath made of one all nations of men to dwell upon the face of the earth'" (CINR:2:q-25). Blacks could find "Negro saints" in its calendar (CINR:39), could observe Negroes occupying imporE. W. Blyden's Legacy 127 tant "civil, military and social positions" in Catholic countries (CINR:225), and benefitting from political freedom (CINR:46). Thus, Negroes were able to see the Chun;~ itself relying on indigenous elements and agencies for its development (CINR:167). This eulogy of the Church of Rome is fund;imentally a criticisrn of Protestant policies. However, Blyden recognized the relatively positive effects of five American denominations (Baptists, Methodists, Episcopalians, Presbyterians, and Lutherans) established on the 'West African coast, where "numerous churches have been organized and are under a native ministry, and thousands of children are gathered into schools under Christian teachers" (CINR:49). But on the whole, he judged the results to be very \Veak: these churches are "in their largest measure ... confined almost exclusively to the European settlements along the coast and to their immediate neighbourhood" (CINR:49-50). At the end of his life, Blyden was quite pessimistic about missionary activities. lln 1910, in a letter to R. L Antrobus, assistant under-secretary at the British Colonial Office, he complained about "teaching mistakes" that created "a gulf between aborigines and colonists" (LET:499). \What was to be done for the successfui promotion of Christianity in Africa? "lin view of the serious obstacles which have so far confronted the work of African evangdization and civilization through European agency, i.t is a matter of serious concern among Christian workers as to how the work should be done" (CINR:160). His answer was clear and simple and followed from his racial views: only peoples of African descent could successfully evangelize the continent: "The method, the shnple holding up of Jesu.s Christ; the instrument, the African himsdf" (CJ.NR: 161). Thus, at the very beginning of the second evangelization of Africa in the nineteenth century, Blyden caUed for an African Christianity. The new faith 1;vould be propagated by black missionaries and its significance would be transformed. He advocated the translation of the Gospel into African tongues, which would "be far rnore effective instruments of conveying to the native mind the truths of the Gospd than any European language" (CINR:68), Bearing in mind Islam's ideological impact on African peoples (CINR:231), he fervently envisioned an authentic African Christiwity. His metaphor was the meeting of PhiHp the aposde and the eunuch from Ethiopia: "Philip was not to accompany the eunuch, to water the seed he had planted, to cherish and supervise this incipient work. If he desired to do so-and perhaps he did-the Spir.it suffered him not, for he 'caught him away'" (CINR:161). The eunuch being the only messenger, he is the only one responsible for "a total revolution in his country through the vvords he had heard." T\!91-iiL.lyen ch writes that though Blyden showed "a distinct partiality for Islam," "he himself never became a lviuslim" (1967:246), in spirit Blyden was a Muslim. He T01as truly concerned, especially in his old age, about the Muslim population and their educ2tion and commercial interests and even identified himself with their fate (see LET:402 and 409). The Muslims caHed 128 The Invention of Africa upon him to aid in their negotiations with the Liberian government (LET:425-27). In a letter to the British Colonial Office, he recognized that the Governor did not pay him "the courtesy due to his office because [he] agree[d] with Mohammedans" (LET:479). In 1877, he stated that he had "more faith in the ultimate usefulness in Africa of the pagan and Mohammedan natives, through Christian influences, than in that of the AmericoLiberians, demoralized by slavery and deceived by a bastard Christianity" (LET:235). In 1889, he confided to F. J. Grimke his long-standing conviction concerning "the superiority of the Soudan or Mohammedan Negroes to others" (LET:406 and 138). He seems to have had a precise objective. In 1888 he wrote: My idea is that Islam is to be reformed and can be reformed. I am now writing ... on 'the Koran in Africa,' discussing its theology and practical teachings in their effect upon the Negro race, and showing how effectively, if Christians understood the system, it might be utilized in the Christianization of Africa. (LET:399) His aim was ambiguous. What did he mean by "reforming" Islam? This is a mystery. What is clear is his critical rejection of "missionary" Christianity. In any case, in 1903 his foremost desire was "to visit the College of Living Oriental Languages in Paris" and also to "visit the famous Mohammedan University at Cairo, the Mosque Al-Azhar, and spend a month there studying their methods" (LET:473). Spiritually and politically, Blyden was, at least from 1900 on, a Muslim. He opposed "the influence of so-called Christianity and civilization" and tended to emphasize the American lesson as he saw it: "in all the long and weary years of the Negro's bondage in America to White Christians-the slaves clung to Christ-but they did not believe in the religion of their white masters" (LET:462). Did Blyden choose between Jesus and Mohammed? There is no answer. Nevertheless, his texts give a clue. What we are dealing with is, without doubt, what one would call nowadays a "theology of difference," simultaneously supported by a racial consciousness and a pluralistic interpretation of the Bible. Such a viewpoint, from Blyden's position, allows for an"original contribution by black Christians: There are stars, astronomers tell us, whose light has not yet reached the earth; so there are stars in the moral universe yet to be disclosed by the unfettered African, which he must discover before he will be able to progress without wandering into perilous seas and suffering serious injury. (CINR: I 51) Complementary to this mission, which only black Christians could successfully carry out (CINR:194), is another one: the promotion of an African nationalism and the unity of the continent. Blyden presented as premises two relevant ideas. On the one hand, there is E.W. Blyden's Legacy 129 the fact that Europe is an invader (CINR:338; L0:73-75). Blyden accepted the truth of the following sentence, written by a European: "the eighteenth century stole the black man from his country; the nineteenth century steals his country from the black man" (CINR:337). On the other hand, there is African opposition to the invasion. Blyden praised the resistance of the Ashanti and the Zulus as an "indication of the suddenness of Africa's regeneration" (CINR:121). The "Economy" of a Discourse It was not the aim of this analysis to describe the historical or sociological climate in which Blyden's ideas evolved. These points have received sufficient scholarly attention (Lynch, 1967; Holden, 1967; July, 1964; Shepperson, 1960). My objective was to present Blyden's "philosophy" from an "archaeologic" viewpoint by uncovering the specificity of his discourse in "the play of analyses and differences" of a nineteenth-century atmosphere, and by looking for discrete relationships between his discourse and some nondiscursive fields. What remains to be said? First of all, Blyden was a strange and exceptional man, who devoted his entire life to the cause he believed in. However, as C. H. Lyons rightly noted, "in seeking to answer the racists in their own terms Blyden developed a theory of race which, while vindicating the black man, derived an uncomfortably large measure of inspiration from late nineteenth-century European race-thinking" (Lyons, 1975:108). The frame of his thinking was a "traditional" one and may be summed up in three oppositions: a racial opposition (white vs. black), a cultural confrontation (civilized vs. savage) and a religious distance (Christianity vs. paganism). His racial theory was simply a relativization of the supposed superiority of the categories white, civilized, and Christian. His discourse, like the racist discourse that he opposed, is purely axiomatic. It is, in the modern sense, a discourse of intimidation; or, to put it in Barthes's language, it is "a language intended to bring about a coincidence between norms and facts, and to give a cynical reality the guarantee of a noble morality." (Barthes, 1979:103). In this sense, it clearly distinguishes itself from the language and the mythologies of the "noble savage." The "noble savage" was a romantic tool, "an aid to self-scrutiny at home" in Europe (Lyons, 1975:8). Even as an anti-slavery weapon, the "noble savage" was an idealized African presenting the most un-African features, and could, for example, "blush" and "turn pale" (Lyons, 1975:7). Blyden confronts these languages and mythologies on "blackness." A. T. Vaughan presents an accurate picture of the context: Virtually all descriptions of the 'dark continent' portray its inhabitants as unattractive, heathen, and grossly uncivil. In theory at least, the Africans' culture could be ameliorated; their physical characteristics could not. And, 130 The lnvemion of Africa although several aspects of African appearance-stature, facial features, and hair texture, for example-displeased the English eye, most striking and dism£bing was the darkness of African skir:. Descriptions of African people invariably stress their biackness, always disapprovingiy. (Vailghan, 1982:919) In this atnJosphere, Blyden simply opposed one racist view to another racist viev,;; precisely by emphasizing anti-mythologies on Africans, their cultu10es, and the necessity of unmixed Negro blood. The ultimate objective of such an anti-racism becomes, almost naturally, the negation of the then-existing povver relationships based on raciai &,tinctions. This process might accourrt for Blyden's conviction about the usefulness of American and '\X,lesItn dian Blacks in the transformation of the African continent, vv-hich is the basis of the project for "racial growth" a11d its myths about racial nationality', black cre2Jivity, and Pa:n-Africanism, In his own terms, the reunion of the "civilized" Christians of the West Indies and America wich their "benighted" brothers in Africa would lead to a positive development from both a cultural and a religious point of view. Blyden's objectives (racial growth, cultural regeneration, Christianization) are a neg2.tion of what he considers African -weaknesses. Fundamentally, the theory is both an argument against the European partition of the continent and a foundation for the ideology that allO'.ved the creation of Llberi.a: "back to Africa." As Blyden grew older, his theory conflicted. ·1vith his pessimistic analysis of black leadership, He continued to think in terms of opposition between "civilization" and "African degenerance," He accepted the efficiency of white colonization. However, w promote more realistically his dream for the transformation of the continent, he opposed the "American-Liberian demoralized by slavery" to the "Mohammedan native" (LET:235). He evea contrasted "bastard Christianity" and its culture with the Islamic faith and its order. He also accepted the "reconstruction" of Liberia under Arnerican protection (LET:496). He knew that "the would-be rulers of rhe land feel it their duty to denounce [him] as a tr2.itor to d1e country" (LET:z35). He was flattered to be considered "the prophet of Libe:-ia" (LET:496) and stated that he had "faith in the ultimate usefulness in Africa of the pagan and Mohammedan nativces, through Christian influence" (LET: z 3 5 ). It is striking that a similar con?iction would later lead the British government to rely on "traditional local authorities as agenci.es of local rnle" (see, e.g., Hailey, 1970:94) for the irr.piementation of "the dogma that civilization vvas a blessing that its possessors ought to spread" (Mair, r975:z52), These theories go together in Biyden's work, contradicting each other and accounting for philosophical inconsistencies, racist propositions, and poHtical opportunisms. As I--L R. Lynch's Edward Wilmot Blyden: Pan-Negro Patriot convincingly demonstrates, at the end of the last century Blyden "had established an intellectual ascendancy in -vf/est Africa, and many \!Vest Africam: vvere prepared w follov1w1h ere he led, but they looked to him in vain for a firn1 and sustained lead, or for dear directives. :Many of them thought his ideas sophistical or contradicted by his actions" (1967:2.46). E. W. Blyden's Legacy 13 I In vvhz:t sense should vve accept Senghor's statement that Blyden was the precursor of negritude and African personality? Jn his forewarcl ,to Blyden's Letters, Senghor himself recognizes that "we had, from time to time" come upon the name of Blyden, but vve had not paid much attention to it ... We had no knowledge of h1icc'io rrespondence, nor of his essays, nor of his weekly nevvspaper with the so signlficant tide of Negro nor, finally, even of his major Yvork, entitled Christianity, Islam, and the Black [sic] Race" (LET:xx). In his intellectual biography, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin et la politique africaine (1962), the name of Blyden is not even mentioned. Aixne Cesaire, Leon G. Damas, and Jacques Rabemenanjara, other members of the negritude movement, never refer to Blyden. h is only in Anglophone -west Africa that Blydlen's real influence may be dearly seen, in Casely Hayford's ideas on '\)'/est African unity, N. Azikiwe's "pan-Negro nationalism," and possibly in Nkrumah's Pan-Africanism (Lynch, 1967:248-50). Blyden vmrked on rnciial issues in the nineteenth centun;; In order ta oppose racist mythologies, he focused on "the virtues of black civilization" and promoted the concepts of "bladrness" and "Negro personality," thus inventing positive nevJ myths about race and the black personality. He had occasional disciples like C. I-fayford and stimulated the nationalism of others, as in the case of 1i:heN igerian Azikiwe. On the whole, the premises and even the essentials of his ideology Yvere already in the air before he explicated his theses. They were present in the racist paradigms that his theses negated and thus might, for example, account for Mary Kingsley's relativist view on races (1965). They had already been used both politically and ideologically by the founders of Liberia (Lynch, 1967: 10-3 r) and by the Haitian revolutionaries, vvho at the beginning 0JI the nineteenth century created the first black republic. At the time of Blyden's death in the first quarter of this century, 1:heses ame premises were incorporated in VJVE. . B. DuBois's Pafr-AfTicamist ideology, and in the 1930s they vvere important in the genesis ,Jf the negritude movement in Pm:is (see '1X'authier, 1964). Let us now take a different look at the ideological significance of Bliyden's ideology. How can we analyze it, and, nmre important, how might it be possible to understand it? Blyden's ideology of Afric::.n identity is a "strain theory" in the sense that it should be understood against "the background of a chronic effort to ,som::ct socio-psychological disequilibrium" (Geertz, 1973:201). This interpretation should explain his suggestion for the replacement of potential European colonizers, coosidered as "invaders," by black peopie:s from America and the \Vest fodies, vvho would become agents for the modernization 21£ Africa. Thus, racial identity stands as an absolute precondition for any sociopolitical transformation of Africa. This choice seems to exclude the possibility of a methodology that, from "the background of a univers2J struggle for 2dvantage," would define an "interest theory." This theory cm present ideal relations: between the Afric2.n process of production and the social rdations of prodw:rion (economic level); between the economic organization and its political reflections and interp.reta132. The Invention of Africa tions (poHtical level); and b.etvveen the idcologic21l structure and frs concrete practice:, with1,n the society (id,eological l,~vel). This theo,y also does so by proposing a type of balance between the eccmomic le·,rel and the ideologjcal superstructures. It is, in principle, capable of generating a new· African mode of prod;1ction, and thus technical modernization, political democracy, and cultural autonomy. Blycilen's "strain r:1eory" remains far from the lAarxist perspective. Its roets are in ithe c,.oci0logy of races and more precisely in the controven;ial pri,nciple of irreconcilable diffen:rn:es between races, Thi~ brings Blyden's thoughl doser to the rornantic philosophies of otherr1ess ,,vh~ch flourished in Europe ckring the nineteenth century and whi.ch largely supported European nati:: malism-in Germany and Italy, for instance---or, a posteriori, ,explained and jnsti.fied them. Neveri:heless, Blyden's perspective is particular. His political ideology 81c:osaes a respons~ to racism and to some of the consequences of imperialism. lt represems an eJTtGtional response m the European process of denigrating Africa and an opposition to the exploitation that resulted from the expansionism of E;ctrope fro.rn the fifteenth century. At the same time, in order to prove its ov.rn significance, his ideology strongly asserts the thesi~ of plurali5m in the hiscorical development of races, ethnic gmups, and nationalitii:; s. Consequently, Blyden can rejecc the evolutionary assumpdcm of "identical but unequal races" vvhkh provides grounds for the theme of the " 1JQ'hitem an's mission" and thus justifi,':'.si mperiafoan and coloni:rntion. In its place, he pUtt3 a different assertion: "distinct but equaL" One canno( but be amazed when analy;dng this thesis, vvhich v,2s the first articubxe nineteenth-cenmry the•ory of "blackness." \Xlhen compared ro Senghor':, negri~ude, the relevance of Blyden'., commitment is still apparent, even ,:hough the concept of race is now generd!y considered an ideological trap. Even in his r•c:'7•:".renfcoer Greco-ftorn!an culture, Blyden announced Senghor. Despite dis.crepanci es due to differences of sosiopolit1:cal contexts, psychok,gi :al ~.ituations,, and phil••Jsophical ref:rences, Senghor, ::,n the whole, pursued Bly::len's 21mbigaous thesis. His pronouncements emph8s.ize th(; African cu1tural and historical identity in terms of race and consider this concept m be essentiaL Blydrn's ideology :s, hovvev:er, mostiy determined by a pmfou11d I.mtderscanding of the burden of slavery~ h is as a negation of thi:, experience that Blyd,~n reconr:mends a rolce for Black .Americans in the modernization of Afr;ca. This important dimension seem2 a defense against the ,c..xperience of domination, and the prospect of Africa's transfor:nation would appear to institu,tienalize a negativity. Sartr-=: put forward a similar theorei.:icaI perspective ir1B lack, Orpheus. Supporting negritude in I...!1egeH::tne1rm s he insisted on its relevance but also c1oted the pertinence of the dialectical contradiction: the racial moment is a1'11ays the promise 0£ another step, ,mother contradiction. The struggle for liberty wodd be won i.n te£ms of a general .cransformatioa of societies and negation of social dasses. This is in ke,eping With the logic of an "imt;;:rest theory." E. 1w". Blyden's Legacy 133 Ai: any rate, Blyden established the "black perscnaHty movernent" which stands for "the sum of values of Afrirnn civilization, the body of qualities \Vhich make up the distinctiveness of 1:hr:p: eople of Africa." This empirical eq11ival,~nt of negritude has been instrumental in sustaining the scrnggle for African independence by opposing colonization ,is a process of falsification and depersonalization of Africans and by criticizing imperialism as a means of exploita1.:io,.-1B. lyden foresaw the immediate future of Africa. As C Fyfe puts it, in the introduction to Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race: Looldng back from the 1960s we can see that in a period equivalent to the span of Bly den's life (he lived to be nearly So) Europeans have: come and gone from the greater part of Africa, les.ving Africans in political control. His reasoning may have been faulty, but his prophecy has been ultimately fu:tilled. Similarly his claim that hundreds of thousands of American Negroes '\!Vere ready to emigrate to Africa seemed, at i:he time, erroneous. Yet the passionate enthusiasm aroused in the United Stares, only a fo-i.;v years after his death, by 1\/farcus Garvey's movement shows that here, too, he saw more deeply than his contemporaries. (CINR:xv) Blydrn expressed the essentials of the black personaiiti/ movement ancl the P:.:m-A_focanispt rogram, vvith its focus on the ideological necessity of becomi11g reconciled with one's herit:.1ge and ifs particular sociohistorica1 experi\~ nce anc'. reality, vrhich presaged Nkrumah's "Consciencism." In the works of lBlyden and Nkrumah, the political philosophy is bs:sed on a framework composed of at least three nwjor s,)urces for inspiration: African tradition, an falamic contribution, and a 'J'/estern legacy. The difference between the t",ATO systems resides in the fact that Nkrumah accepted materialism's presuppositions as the only relev-ant ones and organized his political thought by integrating strain and interest theorfr:s, Bec,1use of his own assumptions, Blyden did not wdd a solid programmatic junctun, between the tension of his wish for poy,7er and the contradictions of his racial anxiety. This failure vvouJd account for his visionary tendency, vvhich led him to make impressive propl:ecies but not always to undertake valid sociohistorical analyses. J\Tonetheless, this difficulty, -,N-hicihs the locus of Blyden's philosophical problems (accounting for ff1ost of his inconsistencies on colonization, structural slavery, Islam's future, etc) paradoxically allowed hin1 to emphasize a relativist view cf history and its interpretations and, thc:refore, the possibilir-y or a general criticisrr, of social sciences. He made this criticism by systematicdly focusing on the significance of European ethnocentrism and its various expressions. This meant, then as now, that an und 1erstanding of African personality or African culture cann:J~ neglect a major cHmension-the epistemological debate. Because of imperiaiis:rn and its ideological reflections in moral and social sciences, this approach must question all discourses interpreting Afric.ms and their culture. Blyden considered this a critical prelimi-nary to establishing a. unifying and prcductive r:ipport between African ideology and the ,concrete practice of knowle6ge. lie 1Nas not until the 1920s 1 34· The Invention of Africa that African inteHectuals redis:::overed Blyden's outlook.: to benefit from the heritage of :their own h~story rather than remaining mere objects of or obedient participants in '~Vesiem social sciences, it was their dur-y to master knowledge of themsdves and their own culture and to open a vigorous debate on the limits of anthropology" What Blyden wrote to J. R. Straton, commenting on a work of one of the most brilliant theorists of racism i.n France, might be applied to him in turn: "Le Bon's Psychology of Peoples ought to be carefully studied" (LET:466). V T'HE Pi\11EJ\JCE OF' PI-lIL()SOPrI~Y "Primitive P:hullosophi.es" La premiere question que je [me] suis posee, rencontrant des paysans [frarn;ais] qui n'etaient ni credules ni arrieres, fut alors celleci: la sorcellerie, est-ce que c'est inconnaissable, ou est-ce que ceux qui le pretendent ont besoin de n'en rien savoir pour soutenir leur propre coherence intellectuelle? est-ce qu'un "savant" ou un "1noderne" a besoin pour se conforter du mythe d'un paysan credule et arriere? JEANNE FAVRET-SAADA, Les Mots, la Mort, les Sorts, The expression "primitive philosophy" was current in the r92os and :i:93os, fo a preceding chapter, I examined at length anthropologists' discourse and both its power and its ambiguity, The concept of "primitive philosophy" is part of this system, which since the end of the nineteenth century had been colonizing the continent, its inhabitants and i.ts realities. lit also belongs to an intellectual edifice built on Levy-Bruhl's work, particularly on such cornerstones as Les Fonctions mentales clans ies societes inferieures (1910), La Mentalite primitive (192::t), L'Ame primitive (1927), Le Surnaturel et la Nature dans la mentalite primitive (193 r), and L'Experience mystique et Jes symboles chez les primitifs ( r 9 3 8 ). They posit a radical difference between the 1JVestc, haracterized by a history 0£ inteHectual and spiritual reasoning, and "primitives," whose life, Weltanschauung, and thinking we11ve ie\X,,eda s having nothing in common vvith the •Y/est, As Levy-Bruhl wrote in La Nlentalite primitive: The attitude of the mind of the primitive is very different. The nature of the milieu in vvhich he lives presents itself to him in quite a different vvay. Objects and beings are all involved in a network of mysticai participation and exclusions. It is these which constitute its texture a!ld order, It is then these which immediately impose themselves on his attention and which alone retain it. (In Evans-Pritchard, 1980:80) 1 35 The Invention of Africa From d-Jtisv iew emerges a theory of two types ,:JJmf entality. One is rntional, functioning accarding to principles of logi.c and inquiring into causal determinations and relations; the other, prdogical, seems completely dominated by cc,lliective representa1ion and strictly depends, upon the law of myst:cal pa.rticipation, "CVestemersp articipate in logical thought. In the prelogical and symbolic, one finds "such peoples as the Chinese included with Polynesi2.ns, I'>Aela•n:; Si.ans,N egroes, American Indi2111s,a nd .Australian Elc1ckfello1;;s" (Evarn-Pritchard, 1980:88), By 1965, E-11ans-Pritchard could state that "there ii.: n::i reputable anthropologist 'Who today accepts this theory o:t t\vo distinct types of mentality" (1980:88). I would only note that what the present-day "grand dichotomy" impiie~ might nor be Levy-Br11hl'sm odel of opposed mentafaies but would surely indicatCe a division of reason between the so-called dosed and open societieso At any rate, in the 1920s and c:.93os the division meant both the t81sk of con1prehending the primitive mentaliry as a poor and non-evolved entiry and the possibiliry of restoring it at the beginning of the history of ::eason. It is withiin. this framework that one understaads such books and contributions dealing with "pri.miti.ve philosophies" as Ddhaisse's Les Idees t'eiigieuses et philoso;/Jhiques des Wat'ega (1909), Kaoze's La Psychologie des Bantu, des Bani Marungu (1907-15n 1), Correfa's Vocab!es philosophiques et 1'eligieux des peuples Ibo (191.5), or the vvell known texts of Brelsford on Priinitive Philosophy (1935) and The Philosophy of the Savage (1938). I arn not sa.ybg that aH vvh,:) ,Nere then studying "primitive organizations" (see Smet, 1978b, 1:975a, :r975)J) were disciples of Levy-Bmhl, defending the thesis of a difference in reason between the "primitive" and the "civilized." Ra:her, all of them, eve.n those who, iike Deiafosse (19.22, 1927), commented upon .African structures and peoples 'Nith a vivid EinfijhJung (sympathy), 'Were concerned •.vitb the discrepancy between Europe and rhe black con,, 1:inent and wished to describe this difference and possibly classify _it into :1 t8.xonomk gnid of human cultures. The Belgian Franciscan Placide Frans T:~1r:_10ea1s s,I indicated iD. my analysis of missionary language, could be considered a paradigmatic ilJustral:i.on of this cur:osixy; He is a sign caught at che crossroads of :;evernl curl'ents: evolutionary assumptions of the late ninf:teentb century, L1§vy-Bruhl's r:1eses on prdoglsm, the European seff-dedared mission to civilize Africans thn::.llgh colonization, 2,nd Christian evangelizatic, n, Within 1:he arrogant frame<.vork 0£ 21. Belgian colonial conquest meant tc:v h:i,st for centuries, Tempels, a missionary in Katanga, wroi:e a small book of philosophy that sdll di.stmbs a number of African thinkers. ';x'hat Tempefo knew of phil0sophy amounted, esseni:iaHy, to the •education he received during his religious training. Fie vvas not a professional philosopher, and hi.s major preoccupations, beginning with his arrival in Africa in 1933, were of a religious r22ture" One or his exegetes, }\.. ], Smet, has suggested that LevyBruhl's influence is evident in the first texts, c,vhich tended tc be ethnographical in oudook, sn:d vvhich Ternpels published before Bantu PhilosoPatience of Philosophy phy (S11:iet,1 9776:77-128). Ternpels wa3 fuHy committed to a mission, that of leading the bbck person (w whc,m he did not yet give the status of being a complete human) along the road to civilization, knov1ledge, and true religion. Hi.s style vvas th2,t of a buianwtari (breakei of rocks), cl spiritual ma:;ter and authoiitarian docto£ (T~mpeb, 196;,.:36). B:mt1,: Philosophy could be consider.<::d a testimony to a revelation and as a sign of a change in the life of Tempels: I must say tb.a, my goal, in thif. study of the Bantu was to feel myself "Bantu" at least o!'ce. I vva11ted to think, Iell, live like him, have a Bantu souL All drnt with the intention of adapting ... There was doubtless in my attitude something moce, or something else, than the simple s•clentific interest of an an-thropologist -✓vho asks questions w,ithout the object of :1i.s science, the living roan in front of him, necessarily beir,g the object:i,e of his invescigatio~,s. JV!.y attitude perhaps induded an elen1ent of sympathy towards this liiving individual and evoked in him a JCeactio,1 of confidence towards me. ('lempeis, 1962:37) Lcoking back ai: the period thai: sa,,v the publication of Bantu Phifosophy, Tempels neatly differentiates himself from anthropologists. His aim is dit-· feren,t, he s2:ys, and depends upon a rndkally different attitude, one of Einfuhlung or sympath:r. Bet his book had extraordina1y repercussions. G. Bachefard greeted it as a treasure. Alioune Diop pledged his faith on thfo litde 'work, appending a foreword to the french version and describing it as the most decisive vvark h1c had ever read (Diop, 1965). However, the hook lies in Kagame's claim that the discovery, through an Aristotelian grid, of hitherto unknown elements of Bantu cultures, is a discovery of a collective, deep, implicit philosophy: "A collective system of profound thought, lived rather than deliberated upon, [of which one can] clearly see the superiority over the solitary labor of a licensed thinker amid a literate civilization" (1976:171). According to Kagame, this silent philosophy can be de~cribed by means of a rigorous application of five major scholastic grids: formal logic, ontology, theodicy, cosmology, and ethics (1956; 1971). Formal logic. This is concerned with the notions or idea as it is expressed in ;:._te rm, of judgement as signified by a proposition, and of reasoning as exercised in a syllogism. Are these notions and relations produced in African "deep" philosophy? Kagame ansvvers yes, noting th,:i_t: (a) Bantu distinguish the concrete from the abstract. Concerping the iatter, a precondition for philosophizing, they separate the abstract of accide11tality (expressing entities which do not exist independently in nature, such as bu-gabo [ virility, courage, force]) from the abstract of substanti;;JivJ (expressing entities existing independently in nature, such as bu-muntu [lmmanity]). (b) The !Bantu proposition is organized in agreement with tvvo principles. The enunciatio:1. of actors' names is always made at the ournet of the discourse. A dassific3tory relative, that is, a linguistic classifier incorporated into subE.:tantives, corresponds to names of each actor and allows a systematic distinction between scbjects and complements in the discourse. (c) The reasoning is elli.~CJtich. may use a premise (major) but more Patience of Philosophy 147 generally it states a general observation or even a proverb directly leading to a conclusion. Bantu Criteriology and Ontology. If in general terms Bantu criteriology does not seem to be particular, nor original when compared to other "analogous" cultures (Kagame, 1971:598), the ontology or general metaphysics is well-educated, thanks to linguistic systems of classes. When one wishes to reach the essential thinking of the Bantu one considers any sample representing the terms belonging to any class. This term represents an idea, designates an object; for instance a shepherd, a child, a robber, etc.; all of these ideas thus represented lead to a unifying notion which is a human being. Similarly: a hoe, a spear, a knife, etc.; each one of these objects corresponds to the already unifying notion of instrument, surely, but if one goes further, the final unifying notion, beyond which there are no more, is the notion of thing. (Kagame, 1971:598-99) There are ten classes in Kinyarwanda. But Kagame, and after him Mulago (1965:152-53) and Mujynya (1972:13-14), emphasize that all the categories can be reduced to four basic concepts (see also Jahn, 1961:100): (a) Muntu = being of intelligence, corresponds to the Aristotelian notion of substance; (b) Kintu = being without intelligence or thing; (c) Hantu expresses the time and place (presents variants such as Pa- in the eastern Bantu languages, Va- in the west and Go- + lo/ro in the south); (d) Kuntu indicates the modality and thus centralizes all the notions related to modifications of the being in itself (quantity or quality) or vis-a-vis other beings (relation, position, disposition, possession, action, passion). As such kuntu corresponds to seven different Aristotelian categories. Bantu ontology in its reality and significance expresses itself through the complementarity and connections existing between these four categories, all of them created from the same root, ntu, which refers to being but also, simultaneously, to the idea of force. Kagame insists that the Bantu equivalent of to be is strictly and only a copula. It does not express the notion of existence and therefore cannot translate the Cartesian cogito. It is by enunciating muntu, kintu, etc., that I am signifying an essence or something in which the notion of existence is not necessarily present (1971:602). When essence (ntu) is perfected by the degree of existing, it becomes part of the existing. The existing cannot be used as a synonym of being there, since in Bantu languages, the verb to be cannot signify to exist. The' opposite of the existing is nothing. In analyzing the cultural elements, one must conclude that the nothing exists and it is the entity which is at the basis of the multiple. One being is distinct from another, because there is the nothing between them. (Kagame, 1971:602-603) Mulago specifies the basic notion of ntu. It cannot simply be translated by being. Ntu and being are not coextensive insofar as the ntu categories only The Invention of Africa subsm,ie created beings and not the original source of ntuJ that is God: Imam:;; In Kinyarwanda and Kirundi, Nyarnuzinda in Mashi (Mui.ago, 1965:153; Kagame, 1956:109-ro). Ntu is the fundamental and referential bssic being-force wbtich dynamically rnanifests itself in all existing beings, difforentiating them but also linking rhem in an ontological hierarchy: The being is fondamentally 011e and all the existing oeings are ontologically attached together. Above, transcendant, is God, Nyamuzinda, the beginning and end of all being; Imana, source of all life, of all happiness. Bet·vveen God 2.nd hmnans are intermediaries, all the ascendams, the ancesrors, the dead members of the family and the old national heroes, all the armies of disencarnated souls. Belovv humans are aH the other beings, who, basically, are only means placed at human's disposition to develop her or his ntu, being, life. (lVidago, 1965:155) In sum, the niu is somehow a sign of a universal similitude. hs presence in beings brings them to life and attests to both their individual value and to the measure of their integration in the dialectic of vital energy. Ntu is both a uniting and a differentiating vital norm which explains the powers of vital inequali1.y i.n terms of difference between beings. It is a sign that God, father of all beings-ishe w'abantu n'ebintu (Mulago, 1965:153)-has put a stamp on the universe, thus making it transparent in a hierarchy of sympathy. Upwards, one vvould read the vitality that, from minerals through vegetables, animals, and humans, links stones to the departed and God. Downwards, it is a genealogical filiation of forms of beings, engendering or relating to one aaother, all of them witnessing to the original source that made them possible. One recalls Foucault's comment upon the prose of the world in the predassical age of the \West: Ev,::ry resemblance receives a signature; but this signature is no more than an intermediate form of the same resembb.nce. As a result, the totality of these marks, slidiing over the great circle of similitudes, forms a second circle which would be an exact duplication of the first, point by point, were it not for that tii:y degree of displacement which causes the sign of sympathy to reside in an analogy, that of analogy in emulation, that of emulation in conveniencr::, which in turn requires the mark of sympathy for its recognition. (1973:2,9) '0ve ;;;.re dealing wiith an African "implicit philosophy," which, says Lufulm:bo, comn--:enting upon the Luba notion of being, is essentially dynamic because the subject lives in accordance to a cosmic dynamism (1964:22). E. J\T. C. hiujynya, a disciple of both Tempels and Kagame, proposes the signific:mce of this ontological dynami.sm i.n four principles (1972:21-22): (a) each element in the universe that is each created ntu is a force and an active force; (b) everything being force, each ntu is thus always pan ,-:ifa ern1titude of other forces, and all of them influence ,each other; (c) ever/ ntu can ahvays,, u.nder the influence of another ntu, increase or decrease in its being; and ( d) because each created being can vveaken inferior beings or Pcztience of Philosophy can be weakened by superior beings, each ntu is always and simultaneously an active aDd fragile fo:i-ce. From these principles, Mujynya deduces tv,o corollaries; first, only one who is ontologically superior can diminish the vital force of an inferior being; second, whatever action is decided or taken by a being apropos another being nwdifies the latter by increasing or decreasing his, her, or its vital force. Consequently, one understands why Mulago refers to Bachelard's evaluation of Tempds's Bantu Philosophy and vvritcs that it would be better to speak of Bantu metadynamics rather than metaphysics (lvfolago, 1965:155-56). Theodicy and Cosmology. Although God is the origin and meaning of ntu, he is beyond it to the point that, according w K21game and }.1ulago, one cannot say th<1t God is an essence (Kagame, 1968:2:r5; 1971:603; 1Viulago, 1965:152). God is not a ntu but a causal and eternal being, who in Kinyarwanda is called the Initial One (Iya-Kare) or the Preexisting one (iya-mbe,-e), in Kimndi the efficient Origin (Rugira), and in Mashi the Creator (Lulema). It is therefore improper, in the Efes of 'Bantu' culture to call God the Supreme Being, since He does not belong to the category of beings and on the other hand the qualifier Supreme places him above beings in the same line of ntu. We must call Him the Preexisting One, an attribute that fits the Existing Eternal. (Kagame, 1971:603) Referring to his native Luba language and carefully reviewing Kagame's documentation, T shiamalenga strongly opposes this interpretation. God is essence. He is ntu, even a muntu; and, in the same vein, the human being is, wlthin the dialec'::ic of vital forces, a thing, a h.intu. ITn effect, Tshiamalenga believes that Kagame and his followers, namely, Mulago and Mujynya, are 'Wrong because they forget that prefixing classifiers are formal and arbitrary, and are used to classify and distinguish the status of substantives, not that of ontological entities (Tshiamalenga, 1973). As to Bantu cosmology, according to Kagame, it is based on an implicit metaphysic principle: every body, every extension has a limit; differently stated, an umlin1ited extension is impossible (Kagame, 1971:606). It follows that the Bantu Weltanschauung distinguishes three circular and communicating worlds: the earth, center of the universe because it is the home of muntu, master of aH existing ntu; above, beyond the sky, the cirde of life in which God dwells; and under our earth the world im which the departed dwell (see also, e.g., Van Caeneghem, 1956; Mbiti, 1971; Bamuinikile, 1971). Rational Psychology and Ethics: In t,;rms of psychology, the reference here is the human being as distinct from the animaL Both are living beings, have senses and the capacity of motion. Both are marked by similar patterns in terms of birth and death. It is, however, in their passing away that a major difference can be observed. The aniffJa!'s vital force or shadmv completely disappears. ln the case of a human being, although shadow usually vanishes, The Invention of Africa the principle of intemgence which charactedzes him as human being remains, becomes the muzimu (modimo, motimo, etc), and joins the subterranean universe. On the other hand, as long as they are alive, animals and human beings are viewed analogically as having two senses (hearing and sight) in comncon rather than the five senses attributed by dassical "IJVe;;tern philosophy. The other three senses are obviously experienced, but according to Kagame, the knoYvledge they bring is integrated into the sense of hearing (Kagame, 1956:186). In terms of ethics, Bantu philosophy can be reduced to two essential principles. (a) The first rule of action and utilization is based on the internal finality of the human being. Kagame notes that if: one looks at the vital principle of a human being, one perceives that it is a t1,J110-pointeadr row: at one end is the faculty of knowing (intelligence) and at the other that of loving (will). Classical philosophy has put the emphasis on the first: we have "to know beings surrounding us in order to discern what is good and what is not good for us. \i7e have to love who and whar is good andl avoid what is bad £or us. At a second step we have to know and love the Preexisting One v,ho made possible these beings so we can know and love them" (Kagame, 1971:608). Bantu philosophy, on the contrary, would emph:isize the other point: loving, and thus procreating, perpetuating rhe lineage and the community of human beings. By doing this it affirms a paradigm: the vital force is immortal. (b) The second rule is related to the preceding one. The Bantu communiiy defines itself through blood filiation. The community stands and understands itself as a natmal and social body and infers from the authority of its being and its histor<; the laws and mechanisms for territorial occupation, political inslitutions, customs, and rites. The most striking and important aspect is that the Bantu community has developed tvvo radically opposed but complementary types 0£ laws. :First, there are juridical laws that the society controls through its judges and lawyers. They do nOi: bind individual ccnsciences, and whoever can escape them is considered intelligent. Second, there are taboo-laws, principally of a religious nature: these are generally negative and dearly specify what should be avoided. They contain in themselves an immanent pov,rer of sanction, and God is the sole judge. Therefore, whatever the transgression, no human being--not even chief, priest, or king-can sanction or forgive the taboo-sin. The problem and its resolution lie betvveen the u:ransgressor and God, and also between his or her stillexisting family on earth and the departed ancestors. Kagame's views may se,em controversiaL They are, however, deductions of a truly impressive and vvell grounded linguistic analysis. No one can seriously question his talent in handling, for example, grammatical overviews of Bantu languages. Nevertheless, many points are questionable, such as the geographical extension and the meaning of the category hantu, or the contigui~y he est;;iblishes between terms and concepts, as if the relationships existing between signi:fiers and signifieds were not arbitrary. At any rate, with Patience of Philosophy Kagame's work, Bantu philosophy escapes Tempels's unsupported generalizations: it is now founded on a linguistic order. A second feature marks the rupture between Tempels and Kagame. Tempels spoke of Bantu philosophy as an intellectual and dynamic system which, although implicit, exists as an organized and rational construction awaiting a competent reader or translator. Kagame is more prudent. He claims that every language and culture is sustained by a deep and discrete order. Yet he insists that his work unveils not a systematic philosophy but an intuitive organization justified by the presence of precise philosophical principles. Moreover, this organization is neither static nor permanent, as indicated by changes in present-day mentalities (1956:27). Despite the evidence of its cultural roots (1976:II7, 225), it should not be reduced to an absolute alterity. The third distinction is that for Kagame it would be nonsense to proclaim an absolute otherness since such important notions as idea, reasoning, and proposition cannot be thought of as offering a Bantu particularity. In the same vein, formal logic as such does not present a definite linguistic character (1956:38-40), and insofar as criteriology and the properties of intelligence are concerned, the problems of the former are co-naturels to all human beings (1976:105) and those of the latter depend on philosophy as a universal discipline (1976:241). There is thus a clear universalist dimension in Kagame's philosophy. The fourth and last major point distinguishing Kagame from Tempels concerns Bantu philosophy as a collectively assumed system. For the Belgian Franciscan, this philosophy is a silent domain which has been functioning for centuries, perhaps in a sort of "frozen dynamism." Kagame, on the contrary, names the founding thinkers of a system that for him is in its being a formulation of a cultural experience and its historical transformations (1976:193, 305). These thinkers are the historical fathers of the Bantu cultures (1976:193, 238), the creators of our languages (1976:83) and the first Bantu humans (1976:76). These four differences about Bantu philosophy-the method for revealing it, whether Bantu philosophy is a systematic or an intuitive philosophy, whether it is a strictly regional or a universalist-oriented system, and whether it is a collective philosophy with or without authors-indicate a clear discontinuity from Tempels to Kagame. Yet elements of continuity exist in both the fluctuation that these differences imply and in the objectives of Bantu philosophy itself. For Tempels, as well as for Kagame and his followers, the affirmation and promotion of African philosophy meant a claim to an original alterity. Their argument, in its demonstration, runs parallel to primitivist theories on African backwardness and savagery. If there is a dividing line between the two, it is a blurred one established primarily as a signifier of sympathy or antipathy. Tempels exploited visible signs of Bantu behavior in the name of Christian brotherhood. Kagame and most of his disciples implicitly or explicitly refer to a racial duty (Kagame, 1956:8) and stress the right to demand "an anthropological dignity" and "the assessment of an intellectual independence" (N'Daw, 1966:33). Once this difference is The Invention of Africa established, cne can note the Hnk from Tempels to Kagame and other "etJmophil.osophe,s." It is a body of judgments stemming from their analyses and imerpretation of African culnu-es and can be summed up in three propositions: (1) a good application of dassical philosophical grids demonstrntes beyond doubt that there is an African philosophy which, as a deep system, underlies and sustains African cultures and civilizations; (2) African philosophy is fundamentally an ontology organized as a deployment of interacting but hierarchically ordered forces; (3) Human vital unit"/ appears to be the ceni:er of the endless dialectic of forces which collectivdy determine i:hei.r being in rdation to human existence (Eboussi-Boulaga, 1968:23-2.6; Hountondji, 1977; Tshiamalenga, 1981:178). These principles sanction the domain of ethncphilosophy, vvhose geography is characterized by two features. The first is z break with the ideology inherent in the anthropologist's techniques of describing African Weltanschauungen. The second is a paradoxical dai111 according to which a satisfactory \\'/estern methodological grid is a requirement for reading and revealing a deep philosophy through an analysis and an interpretation of linguistic structures or anthropological patterns. So far, it has been possible to distinguish two principal orientations within this field: the first interrogates and explores the so-called silent philosophy (e.g., A, Makarakiza, 1959; E Ablegmagnon, 1960; "(!!. Abraham, 1966; Lufoluabo, 1962, 19646; l'-J'Daw, 1966; J.C. loahoken, 1967; J. Jahn, 1961; Mujynya, 1972; 012yew11eni, 1982). The second orientation studies this philosophy vvith r historical trends: the first two are an anthmpoiogical philosophy or erhnophilosophy and 2.n ideological philosophy or political philosophy-two currents that, in a mythical or nationalist way, contributed to the promotion of African dignity and political independence, Evfore recendy has emerged a post-independence trend: the critical one, which with Crahay, Hountcndji and others demands a rigorous reflection on the conditions of philosophy as ·well as on the conditions of existing individuals and soci,etles (Elungu, 1978). Foundations .Att he other ';':Xtremef rom ethnophilosophy and its critics, one finds vvorks that have neither the form of amh:mpological exegeses nor the fashionable anti-;:;thnophilosophical vocabulary. They not only fit fa.ithfuHy into the mainstream of the phiiosophia perennis but sometimes indeed deal with specifically 'v/estem topics. lvfany ot the advanced degrees 2cwarded in European imiversities to young African scholais attest to this uend. These scholars single out the mfrv-ersal historicity of a mechod. One can begin by refer6ng to applied philosophy, as iHustrated by Aguolu's study on "John Dew--ey's Democratic Conception and hs Implication for Devdopi.ng Countries'' (Aguoiu, 1975) and m:::ire recently by Hallen and Sodipo's book on Knou1ledge, Belief and 1,Vitchcraft (1936). ~:t✓-e shall refer as weH to the best papers, published annually by the department of philosophy of the Faculte de Theobgie Cathc,Eque i.n Ki11Shasa. (They are among those ;,r,rhose major rderen;::es accidentally co1ncide \Vith the Franco-Belgian orthodoxy in philosophy") Vile sh;:dl also refet to Vf/iredu's very British Philosophy and an A.fri:;an Cultttte ( I 9 3o ), which ;c~mong other things "teaches" us that "iI is a fact that Africa lags behind tbe '1Ji/esti n the cultivation of rational inquiry" (:::980:43) and ind.icates that "the id,eal --..rvtJoy reform backward customs in Africa ;11usrt, surely, be to undermine their found,ation in s:.1perstition by f,'.Jstering in the people ... rhe spirit of rational inquiry in all spheres of th,)ughi: and bdief" (198c,:45). There are in this special area quite orthodox and apparently purely spec:- The Invention of Africa ulative undertakings but also some imeHectual surprises. f.lodunrin's essay ,ryn "The Alogicality of Imrntortality" ( I 97 5 b) and "\1viredu's "Logic and Ontology" (1973) are exemplary. h1 terms of volumillous contributions I may suggest three m.ode1s: Elungu's systematic study on the concept of extent in M::deb::anche's thought (19736), Ugirashebuja's book on dialogue and poetry according to Heidegger (19n), and Ngindu's research on the philosophical problem of religious knovvledge in Laberthonniere's thinking (1978). How can these ch0ices of subject be justified? fr is difficult to read authors' minds. The social and intellectual context in whi.ch these philosophers developed might account for their choices, just as it would for such notorious eighteenth-century cases as the African A. G. Amo's intellectual career in what was not yet Germany and his works De Humana Nientis Apatheia (1734), Tractatus de Arte Sobrie et Accurate Philosophandi (1738), and the lost De Jure Maurorum in Ei-,ropa (1729). Another case, this one scandalous, was that of Jacobus Capitein, an African who -wrote and publicly presented a study at Leiden University in the Netherlands on the nonexistent opposition between shwery and Christian freedom: De Servitude, Libertati Christianae non Comraria (1742). At any rate, cur contemporary students of philosophia perennis may also be troubling. One is surely taken aback when, in examining these very classical analyses, o:r:e comes across presuppositions on African otherness in the guise of iogical deduction. For exam.pie, it is a surprise to follow Ugirashebuja discovering in Heidegger's writing Banyarwanda's language as a sign of being ancl its nomination, and to discover in the Rvvandese philosopher's text the voice of I--:Iei.deggeirn viting aH of 11s-T•Jlfestemers, Africrns, Asians-to listen to being in our respective ianguages (see Ugirashebuja, 1977:227; Dirven, 1978:rnr-6), In the same vein, Ngindu, in a snphisticated introduction to the fin de siecle modernist crisis within the Roman Catholic European cirdes of philosophy, digs up reasons for commenting on cultural imperialism in Africa and its epistemological force of reduction (Ngi11du, 1978:19). In this philosophical practice, which is completely foreign to African culture, or at best, a marginal but powerful space in ·which only ways of domesticating the African eq:ierience are elaborated, slips of the pen sometimes occur and rni.mrmrs are heard v1hich resemble ethno-philosophical dreams, On the orher hand, as the School of Kinsh,tsa has demonstrated, it is not at aH cerrai.n that Hountondji and his fellow anti-ethnophilosophers are neocolonialist devils pre·,enting people from affirming their otherness, Strangely enough, his responses to criticisms (Hountondji, 1980; 1981; 1982), :"·eflecta well-balanced philosophical ,:1,.nnda tionalist imagination: "as Gramsci rightly used to say, only truth is revolutionary" (19!h:67). Both 1:he ethnophilosophical trend and the critical school agree on their positJ:on about the existence of philosophy as an autocritical exercise and a critical discipline in Africa. Viewed in terms of its organic expression, this practice can be described from aJ least four different angles: the Ethiopian heritage, the solidity of an empiricist tradidon in English-speaking countries, Patience of Philosophy the debate about the epistemological foundation of an African discourse in social and human sciences, and IVlarxist universalism. h1y brief pm,entation of Smnner's editions of Ethiopian texts (see appendix) shows the particular situation of the Ethiopian tradition, whose Chrlstianity goes bask as far as the fourrh centUP/. Since that time, mon\:s and scholars have been at work on intellectual arguments, theological and political commen::aries, and translations. Through the ages, a philosophy took shape. i\ccording to Samner, The Boo1~ of the Wise Philosophers (see Sumner, 1974) and The Treatise of Zar'a Yacob (Sumner, 1978) are good examples. The first "presents itself as the quintessence of what various philosophers have said on a certain number of topics, most of which are ethical" (Sumner, :::974:100). Thus philosophy, fi:ilasfa, is understood as being principally a wisdom, vvhich includes both ,I knowledge of the universe 2.ad mankind's pt,rpose in life. Adapted maxims from the Greek, Egyptian, and Arabic as v.reH as maxlic.1s from Ethiopian Ir9.dition (as in the case of many numerical proverbs) guide the listener or the reader on topics such as matter, human physiology and psychology, man's social dimension, and n-::oral concerns (Sumner, 1974). The Treatise of Zav'a Yacob also presents prnpositions on :11oral issues (Sumner, 19 8 3) and guidance about knowledge. Yet it is a unique and lrnportant sign which suggests a critical outlook in the seventeenth-century Ethiopian cultufe, to the point that A, Baumstark has compared it to "the Confessions of a fdlmv African, St. Augustine" (ir: Sumner, 1978:5). The method of Zar'a 'facob is definitely new: it posits the light of reason as a "discriminating criterion between vvhat is of God and what is of rr1en" and can be compafed to Descartes's dear idea (1978:70-71), Another side of the foundation of African philosophical practice is the viability of the empiricist method in Anglophone countries. Their universi1: ies and philosophy departments are generally older, Van Parys, after a visit to twenty African crnmtnies having university departments of philosophy; noted in his evaluative synthesis that in Anglophone countries they were bet 1:er organized and appeared more solid in .:heir already tested traditions. (Van Parys, 1981:386). More directly, the quality of the biannual journal Second Order clearly preserves a sense of academic heritage. Its aim is to publish first dass phitosopnical work of all kinds, but it is especially concerned to i::ncourage philosophizing with special reference c:o African context. Although the initiators 1Jelong to the Anglo-Saxon tradi::ion of philosophy, they see ir as their job to construe their subject rather widely: 1:0 regard inter-discipliaary boundaries as made for m,rn, not m:m for them, and to watch ou, for growing points in their subject as it appli,es itself to ,,ew problems, (Cover of issues: 2) K. Win:du's elegant book (1980) is a good example of this ambitio11c In fact, ,what determines the con6guration of this empiricist practice is the very close relationship existing between Anglo-Saxon philosophers and their African_ colleagues. For example, Second Order's board of consuhants indudes The Invention of Africa D. Emmet (Cambridge), E. Gellner (Cambridge), D.W. Hamilyn (London), R. Harre (Oxford), R. Horton (Ife), D. Hudson (Exeter), S. Lukes (Oxford), J.J. Macintosh (Calgary), and A. MacIntyre (Brandeis). Also, in Anglophone countries teaching and research in philosophy are accepted as a given, and the departments are well distinguished from departments of African religions or sociology. A third orientation in the practice of philosophy in Africa is the search for the epistemological foundation of an African discourse. We shall examine a few illustrative cases: the epistemological debate on African theology, the discussion on the significance of social sciences, and the deconstruction doctrine in philosophy. An important debate on African theology took place in 1960 (Tshibangu and Vanneste, 1960), stemming from a public discussion between A. Vanneste, dean of the School of Theology at Lovanium University and one of his students, T. Tshibangu, who later became the Roman Catholic auxiliary bishop of the archdiocese of Kinshasa and rector of the university. When the university was nationalized in 1971 by the Mobutu government, Bishop Tshibangu became the president of the National University of Zai:re. The debate concerns the possibility of an African Christian scientific theology. Tshibangu stated that under present world conditions it makes sense to promote the feasibility of an African-oriented Christian theology that epistemologically would have the same status as the Judea-Christian, Eastern, and Western theologies. Dean Vanneste, although believing in the future of Christian theology in Africa, insisted on the demands of theology understood in its strict sense and defined it as a universal discipline (see Nsoki, 1973; Mudimbe, 198ra; Ngindu, 1968 and 1979; Tshibangu, 1974). At stake is the legitimacy of an exploratory inquiry: can one reconcile a universal faith (Christianity) and a culture (African) within a discipline (theology) that is epistemologically and culturally marked? (Tshibangu and Vanneste, 1960: 3 3 3-3 5 2). In a great confusion, European and African scholars, notably J. Danielou, A.M. Henry, H. Maurier, V. Mulago, Ch. Nyamiti, A. Janon, and G. Thils (see Bimwenyi, 198ra; Mudimbe, 198ra) took sides. The debate also questioned indirectly the form and the meaning of the African presence in the field of Christian theology. This debate could only lead to an evaluation of the strictly scientific orientation of the Lovanium School of Theology. The School's intellectual configuration was subordinated to a number of principles (scientific rigour, theological tradition, and dogmatic vigilance) in the manner of the best European Catholic institutions. This cult of scientific quality is exemplified in such contributions by Zai:rean theologians as Tshibangu's work on the complementarity between "speculative" and "positive" theology in the history of the Western Church (1965), Atal's philological analysis of John's prologue (1972), Monsengwo's semantic study of the Bible (1973), and Ntendika's books on patristic philosophy and theology (1966, 1971). In which sense are these Patience of Philosophy highly sophisticated studies related 1:0 the COP.Crete condition of African Christians, their human probJ.ems and spiritual hope? The problem extends i:o alll the social and! human sciences ·md has been enlarged npon as both an epistemological and a ;:iolitical problem b7 the second meeti.ng of Zai:rean philosophers in Kinshasa in 1977 (see also Adotevi, 1972; Bimwenyi, 198ra; Buakasa, 1978; Sow 1977, 1978). W!e have seen that anthropoiogical discourse was an ideological discourse. In rhe same vein, contemporary African discourse is Ideological too, and as a discourse of political power, it often depends upon the same type of ideologies (Hauser, 198:!.; Elungu, 1979). Gutkindl think$ that "actual intensification of: capitalist control over the means of _production in Africa increasingly reduces sections of the population to a landless mral or mba:J' proletariat in whose Hve ancestral traditions, hovv:ever modified, no longer mean anything" (in 1V1acGaffey, 1981). I would adrl that this has another significance. Large sections of the African people have nothing to do with the present-d2.y economic ancl political structures within their own countries, nor 'Nith intellectuals' and universities' proj,ects for linking \/Ve::;tern experience to the African context. It is because of this situation that both the African .i'vlarxists and "deconstructionists"- the latter in harmony with the anti--ethnophHosophy current-- base their arguments. For 1bvra, for example, the critical enterprise is a total vocation. The esprit critique must 2.pply indiscriminately to European intdlectual imperatives and to Africaa constructions, the only acceptable "trnth" being that there is nothing sacred that philosophy cannot interrogate (Iowa, 197rb:30). Hountondji goes further, stating that philosophy is essentially history and n.ot system, amd thus there is no single doctrine that may daim truth in an absolute m,m.ner. The best understanding of truth resides in the process of looking for i1t "In a way, then, truth is the very act of looking for truth, of enunciating propositions and trying to jnstify and found them" ([1977] 1983:73). Similar phHosphicali positions aUowed T. Obenga to reinvent the cu.ltura.l relationships that existed between Egypt and Black Africa. Tin tlhe process, he criticized European theses and pinpoints Cheikh Anta Diop's methodologicd we2,knesses. And J, Ki-Zerbo's g::neral history of Africa (1972) provoked a new thinking about the diversity of functions of African cultures. AJl of the social and human sciences underwent this radical experience between 1950 and 1980. Fundamentally, the questioning is based on "the right to truth," implying a new analysis of three paradigms: philosophical ideal versus contextual determination, scientific authoriry versus sociopolitica: power, and scientific objectivity versus cultural subjectivity. Yet there are signs that, since the end of "\WorldV 7ar H, have meant the possibility of new theories in the African field:, European theorists, then, seem to invert some values of colonial sciences and analyze African experience from a perspective that gradu;::;.Hy institutionalizes "che themes of contextual deterThe Invention of Africa miHation and cultural subjectivity. In the 19 50s, J. Vansina and Y. Person envisaged a nev,r arrang,::n1ent of the African past, interpreting legends, fables, and ora: traditions as "texts" and "documents," which with Ihe help c,f archaeological da[a could contribute to the foundation of an "ethnohistory," a discipline joining history and anthropology (Vansina, 1961). Jn the same period, G. Balandier wrote the first books on "African sociology." Moreover, with his anthropologie dynamique, he reorganized the discipline and described the traditional "object" of anthropology, the "native," as the only possible "subject" for his own modernization. In the psychological field, scholars such as A. Ombredane re-examined, on a regional basis, the assumptions concerning the psychology and intelligence of blacks (1969). Frantz Crahay confronted Tempels's heritage, J. Jahn's generalizations on African. culture, and the limitations of Nkrumah's philosophy; and proposed conditions for a critical philosophical maturity in Africa (196 5). In the 1970s G, Leclerc, vrith Anthropologie et colonialisme (1972), and J. L Calvet, with Linguistique et colonialisme (1974), among others, rewrote the history of ideological conditioning in the social and human sciences. Th.is trend of Western scholarship has had an impact on African practice, Nevertheless, it is neither a direct ancestor nor the major reference for the African current we are examining. Although both are concerned with the same object, and both present, essentially, the same fundamental objective, there are at least two major differences that distinguish them. The first difference accounts for a paradox. These cmrents have the same origin in the '0Vestem ez)isteme, buit their beginnings did not coincide, and despite their similari~ they consi:itute two autonomous orientations. They have all devdoped in the European context as "amplifications" of theses coming from two loci. The first of these i\s the "library" constructed by such scholars as Frobenius, Delafosse, Theodore Monod, Robert Ddavignette, B. Malinowski, and Marcel Griaule; the second, the intellectual atmosphere of the r 9 3 os-1940s and surely the I 9 5 os, which with the rediscovery of Marx, Freud, and Heidegger produced a critical reevaluation of the significance of links between objectivity and subjectivity, history and reason, essence and existence. On the basis of these questions, new doctrines appeared: neoMarxism, existentialism, and also negritude and black personality. These emphasized in different ways the pertinence and the importance of subjectivity, the unconscious, existence, reiativity of truth, contextual difference, and otherness, In this atmosphere, Africanism developed and took on 2i new visage. In the 1950s and 1960s, while in Anglophone ccuntries JVL Herskovits and B. Davidson promoted a new interest in African culture, the most dynamic schools of European Africanism in Francophone countries were 1Vfa.rxistdominated and heavily influenced by Levi-Strauss's notions of "otherness" and "savage mind," It is an Africanism of "big brothers." Y. Benot, C. Coquery- Vidrovitch, L. de Heusch, C. Meillassoux, H. Moniot, J. Suret-Canale, B. Ve chaegen, others main methodological points: the choice of a rigorous classical analysis of the \Y/estern historical process of indigenizing the Gospd and a :::ritical interpretation of this process, based on the ideological significance of strategic cultural selections and subservient rules and aimed at the explanation of the progressive constitution of the Church's doctrine and the development of Patience of Philosophy 171 itts Htmgy. Bishop Tshibangu's work on the history of theological methods in the West (1965, 1980), J. l\Ttendika's careful studies (1966, 1971) on patristic theology, and Kinyongo's exegetical synthesis of the meaning of Jhwh (1970) are good examples of the trend. In philosophy, the sc:.me tendency to seek a good understanding of the T\JVesterpnr actice of philosophy, as a useful step prior to promoting African philosoyhy, can be observed in sev:cral cases. Second Order's orientation, Ehmgu's study of the c.Jncepts of space and knowledge in Malebranche's philosophy (1973b), Ugirashebuja's analysis of the relationship between poetry and chought in Heidegger's work (1977), and l\Jgindu's presentation of religious knowledge according to Laberthoniere (1978) provide examples. This critical reading of the 'vvestern experience is simultaneously a way of "inventing" a foreign tradition in order to master its techniques and an ambiguous strategy for implementing alterity. In theology, for instance, it is accepted that "African theologians have nothing w gain by withdrawing into themselves. [By so doing] they would condemn themselves to remaining second-rate theologians" (Tshibangu and Vanneste, 1960:333-52). Kn 1974, Tshibangu published Le Propos d'une theologie africaine, a brief manifesto which concentrates on linguistic and cultural relativism and upholds the evidence of ethnic urn::lerstanding and expressions of Christianitl;~ along with the fact that there are a variety of systems of thought. Tshibangu's work has become a dassic and has had tremendous influence. It is already possible to study the outcome of his thesis. There are more and more anthropological and linguistic investigations of African traditions that pinpoint regions of compatibility and divergence between Christianity and African religions. Examples of this are Bimwenyi's Discours theologique negro-africain (r98rn), Hebga's Sorcellerie et priere de delivrance (1982), the book published by Ela and Luneau, Voici le temps des heritiers (1981), and Hearing and Knowing (1986) by M. A. Oduyoye. Rather than insisting on the economy of cultural and religious constellations and their possible compatibility, this trend tends to emphasize the pertinence of diffraction and its relative value in a regional system of revelation. Mulago's Cahiers des religions africaines has been the most visible locus and vehide for this project since 1965. Oduyoye sums up the nature of this quest: We ... are confronted 'With this fact: those who were fof a long time contect to be consumers of theology have begun to be producers of theology and it is Christian theology. They are widening the panorama of symbols, heightening the color of issues, and demanding comn1itment and action. (Oduyoye, 1986:76. Emphasis mine) I asked Tshibang11 how, in this project for an intellecrnal discontinuit1; and an ideological reversal, he could explain the relationship between thought and action. He answered by specifying the philosophical frame in which this new discourse evolves and the anthropological context of its possibility; 172 The Invention of Africa Mudimbe: In any case concerning your project, one could wonder whether thought could precede action. Surely, this is very scholastic. But people have also said that the most important thing was to practice theology; that the specificity, the African character of the discourse would come naturally. Tshibangu: You are correct in posing the problem of the relationship between thought and action. In reality, being, and consequently life, and action that actualizes it precede thought ontologically. But thought in turn is implied in the "form" of being that gives it the logical character of cognizability and acceptability. In fact the two are correlative and condition each other. In spiritual life, and particularly in a community of life such as the Church, life and doctrine condition one another and act one upon the other. To date the question of African theology is largely one of principle. Existentially concrete problems are perceived and felt specifically by African Christian communities. African theology will realize itself effectively by trying in a radical way to answer the problems posed by the principles of African culture, the evolution of African societies with numerous questions concerning spiritual and ethical problems that are not lacking. [ ... ] Today given the level of awareness of cultural differences, the specificity of cultures is not worked out over a long period of time and in a spontaneous way. We know the conditions of the specificity. This specificity, however, is based on the fundamental unity of human nature. The question is one of determining the framework for the development of this specificity so that it may enrich the total realization of the potentialities that nature has granted to a humanity diversified in its historic and spatial existence. Mudimbe: You are a professor of fundamental theology at the Faculte de Theologie Catholique in Kinshasa. By temperament and by choice you say that you are preoccupied with epistemological questions. For what reason? What exactly are you looking for? Tshibangu: I mean by that that I am always preoccupied with the problem of justification. In the field of action everything must be grounded, and this demand imposes itself especially when in addition one accepts the law of the evolution of things, of institutions, of ideas, of customs. In order not to stray, to make mistakes, to act by simple habit or conditioning, it is necessary to reflect on the foundation of judgements and attitudes. And I intend to proceed methodologically in this search for foundations, in order to propose actions and attitudes that are themselves grounded and well justified, infellectually and with respect to the goals that humans must follow. (In Mudimbe, 1977:18) A last trend in theology addresses a delicate issue: does it make sense to be Christian and African? As the Jesuit priest E. Mveng expressed it more concretely, why should an African believe in and promote a Christianity that not only has become a product of exportation for Western civilization but also has come to be used as a means of racial and class exploitation? Unfortunately the West is less and less Christian; and Christianity, for a long time, has been a product of export for Western civilization, in other words, a Patience of Philosophy perfect tool for domination, oppression, the annihilation of other civilizations. The Christianity preached today, nm only in South Africa, but by the ·\West as a povver and civilization, is far, very far from the gospel. The question is therefore posed radically: what can be the place of Third 'IJVcrld peoples in such a Christianity? And this question is first of ail aimed at the official churches. (Mveng, 1983:140) To face this question, another African Jesuit, Eboussi-Bouiaga, has put forth for consideration his Christianisme sans fetiche: Revelation et domination (1981). It is a deconstruction of Christianity. Setting aside dogmas, traditional criteria, and official Church theories, he propmmds a direct interpretation of revelation as a sign of liberation. In this perspective, the i:ime and the dignity of the human being are seen and defined as the real place of God's dream for incarnation. As a consequence, according to Eboussi-l3oulaga, the most hr.portant issue for followers of Jesus is the liberation of their own faith and its conversion into a practical means for a true transformation of the world. This conclusion is the postulate of theologies of liberation in South Afrirn (see, e.g., Tutu, 1984; Boer::ak, 1977, 1984a, 19846). One of the soundest illustrations of this spirit of the Exodus is in J. M. Ela's Le Cri de l'Homme Africain: Questions aux Chretiens et aux Eglises d'Afrique (1980). Ela caHs for a "radical move away from the God of natural theology preached by missionaries" and an invocation of the God of Exodus, interested in history and the soci.oeconomi.c conditions of humans. Strictly speaking, this is a political discomse in the name of Christian prophetisrn. We have justified slavery, violence and vvar; we have sanctified racism and split our churches on the issue of the preservation of white supremacy. 'W/e have discriminated 2:gainst women and kept them servile whilst we hid our fear of them behind daims of "masculinity" and sanctimonious talk about Adam and Eve. We have grown rich and fat and pm,;erful through the exploitation of the poor, which we deplored but never really tried to stop. All in the name 0£ Jesus Christ and his gospel. Now this same gospel speaks to us, and we can no longer escape its demands. h calls us to love and justice and obedience. We would like to foHill that calling, but we do not wwt to risk too much. The Reuben option. The Reuben option: Take a stand, bm always cover yourself. (Boesak, 19846:38) A hermeneutical school appeared in this context as the site of a more mlmrally oriented research in African theology. I think that Okere's D.Phil. dissertation (1971) was the first major initiative. Hm;vever, it is Tshian.1.alenga (1973, 1974, 19776, 1980) and t,Tkombe (1979) who have become thi.s school's most productive exponents. Okolo made explicit the philosophical choices of the method (1980), dr8sving new propositions from 2, brief and stimulating text by his former professor, Kinyongo (1979). Okere published in 1983 an extract of his D.Phil. dissertation concerning the foundations of the method. In this work one finds dear guidelines based on the solid principle that while "language seems to affect culture and thought at some The Invention of Africa level," it does not follmv that one can "speak of philosophical and m1etaphysical thought as somehmv predetermined linguistically" (Okere, 1983:9). The most convincing studies to date, apart from Okere's unpublished dissertation, bave been those of Tshiamalenga (e.g., 1974, 19776, 191fo) and Nkombe in his methodological propositions (e.g., 1977, 19786) and his study of metaphor and metonymy in the paroemiologic symbols of the Tetela language (1979). In terms of intellectual classification, it is possible to distinguish two main trends. The first is one of ontdogj_cal hermeneutics, which at least in Kinshasa coincides with the reconversion of Tempels and Kagame's Iegacy to more rigourous rnoclalities of philosophizing (see, e.g., Tshi.amalenga, 1973, 1974,, 1980). The second is more of a psychosocially oriented hermeneutics which integrates lessons from phenomenological methods (e.g., Laleye, 191h, r982; Nkombe, r979). The question of the significance of these new intellectual strategies of "conversion" has occurred in other domains. In social sciences, T K. Buakasa, for example, has c:nalyzed the sociocultural determinations of scientific reason, under the provocative title, Western Sciences: What For? (1978; see also Okonji, 1975). Inspired by Foucault and especially by J. Ladriere's work on the philosophy of sciences, Buakasa reexamines the historicity and archltecture of scientific reason in order to introduce techniques for the conversion of African "mentality" in terms of scientific reason. Another philosopher, P, E. Elungu, accepts the realir-y of African authenticity and the relative autonomy of its socioh1storical experience, but bases his proposals for African liberation on a unique condition: a conversion to philosophical and critical thinking. According to him, this spirit appears to be the only possible way to modernization, insofar as it will mean in African tradition the possibility of a rupture and subsequently the emergence of a scientific mentality, This is a new cultural environment characterized by: (a) man's capacity to break with what is simply given, in the pursuit of that ,Nhich is essential and specific to him; (b) the seizing of this essential specificity in freedom of discourse, and ( c) the realization that this freedom of 3i.scourse is not freedom itself, that this autonomy of discourse is not independence. (Ehmgu, 1976; see also Sodipo, 1975, 1983). Examining these new rules of the game, one recalls Foucault's objectives for the liberation of discourse in The Discourse 011 Language (in appendix, 19lh). Explicit references to V✓estem schemata are also noticeable in I-Iountondji's program on the African practice of science, which relies on Altl: ms:;er, and in Nkombe's research on African symbols inspired by Ricoeur and Levi-Srcrauss. But these intellectual filiations imply methodoiogi.cal and ideological syntheses rather than the capitulation of otherness (Vilasco, 1983). Hmmtondji presents the ambiguous dream of present-day African philosophers provocatively: The problem , .. as regards our z.ttitude townds our collective heritage, is how to respond to the challenge of cu!tu_ca! imperialism without imprisoning f\·t',,_:., :}), :,:, f. t~-·· f) :f· 1'/ ~-,' ,.,:, •fs ,# fJ. ~f/ l~. t f'J", I f i:-' :41 ~t', :~t I:,· l f,f l I l~ ·-· ~t I'. ();, Patience of Philosophy 175 ourselves in an imaginary dialogue with Europe, how to re-evaluate our cultures without enslaving ourselves to them, hovv to restore the dignity of our past, vvithout giving room to a passeistic attimde. Instead of bliDdly condemning our t;:aditions on behalf of reason, or rejecting the latter on behalf of the fonner, or making an absolute of the internal ra-cionality or these traditions, it seems more reasonable to me to try and know our traditions as they were, beyond any l'nythology and d:istortion, r:ot merely for t;1e purpose of selfidentification or justification, but in order to help us meet the chalienges and problems of today. (1983: r.1.2-43) To sum up the rules of this deconstmcdon, I note three major objectives: (a) to understand and define the configura!ion of scientific practice in social and human sciences as an ideological locus determined by three major variables-time, space, and the (un)conscious of the scientist; (b) to analyze and understand African experiences as formed on the basis of a particular history and as witnessing to a regional Weltanschauung; and (c) to think about and propose reasonable modalities for the integration of African civilizations into modernity, this in accordance with critical thinking and scientific reason, for the purpose of the liberation of man, It might be that all of these themes have been made possible by soi:ne of the consequences of rhe epistemological rupture, v,hich according to Foucauh (1973) appeared in the -west at the end of. the eighteenth centu'.1 . The hypothesis makes sense if one looks at the progressive recession, from the :1i.neteenth century through the r93os, of theories about "function," "conflict," and "signification," and at the slow emergence of a new rnnderstanding of the potentialities of paradigms of "norm," "rule," or "system." In theory, this reversal accounts for all ideologies of difference (see, e.g., Ricoeur, 1984). However, it is not certain that it fully explains the functional arrangement of the "colonial library," its histor1 and pervasive effectiveness during the nineteenth and the twentieth centuries, nor the ambiguous relationships berween the myths of the "savage mind" 2.nd the African ideological strategies of otherness, Horizons oi Knm1vledge The history of knmvledge in Africa and "bout Africa appears deformed and disjointed, and the explanation lies in its own origin and development. As in the case of other histories, we fuce vvhat Veyne has called "the illusion of integral reconstitution [which] comes from the fact d1at the documents, which p:-ovide us with the answers, also dictate the questions to us" ( 19 84: r 3 ), Furthermore the body of knowledge itself, whose roots go as far back as the Greek and Roman periods, in its constitution, organization, and paradoxical richness, indicates an incompleteness and inherently biased perspectives. The discourse which witnesses to Africa's knowledge has been for a long time either a geographical or 211 anthropological one, 21I any r::te a "discourse of competence" about unknow11 societies v1ithout their own The Invention of Africa "texts." Only recently has this situation been gradually transformed by the concept of ethnohistory, which in the 1950s postulated the junction of anthropological topoi with those of history and other social sciences, and later on integrated oral tradition and its expressions (poetry, fixed formulas, anthroponymy, toponymy). In so doing, this discourse began constructing simulacra about the relations existing between present African social organizations and history. On the whole, the discourse on African realities offers two main characteristics: on the one hand, it is a heterogenous discourse emanating from the margins of African contexts; and on the other hand, its axes as well as its language have been limited by the authority of this exteriority. The atmosphere of the 1950s meant a new valorization in the Africanist discourse, namely, the promotion of another center: history and its ideological activity. This valorization is well represented in the shift that occurred progressively after the 1930s, moving from the anthropological authority and its negation of African historicity to the respectability of a possible historical knowledge of so-called traditional societies. This shift is illustrated by Herskovits (1962) and Vansina (1961). During the same period, other forms of languages were being derived from the same value presuppositions and freeing themselves from the anthropologist's intellectual space (see, e.g., Wallerstein, 1961, 1967). Religious thinking began to conceptualize a history and a sociology of what Schmidt called "primitive revelation" (1931) and, as in the case of Des pretres noirs s'interrogent ( 19 5 6), to seek regional platforms for an African Christian theology. With Griaule and Tempels, the reading and interpretation of local cultures had already challenged the narrowness of classical ethnography and the gospel of its topoi and raised questions of local rationalities and African philosophy. J. Copans insists on the advent of sociology and Marxism as major events which characterize this intellectual evolution of Africanism (in Gutkind and Wallerstein, 1976). "Sociology was not just a new specialization, it constituted a complete break on several counts; empirically, as it was taking into consideration the real history of African peoples; in scale, as it moved on from the village to national social group (from 'mini' to 'maxi'); theoretically, as a materialistic and historical explanation took the place o1 Griaulian idealism which ignored the realities of colonialism" (1976:23\ This new Marxist approach was induced in the late 1950s by what Copans calls the "collapse of anticolonial unity." This precipitated the appearance of a new theoretical field of Marxist analysis: the world economic market, struggles for political liberation, the development of social classes, capitalist economies and imperialisms, etc. Thus, after 1956, "Marxist thought found new life" insofar as from a Marxist viewpoint Africa was "a virgin theoretical field." "The use of concepts of the imperialist system or modes of production was facilitated by an explanation in terms of unstable arrangements and the dynamism of contradictions." After the 1960s, "the characteristics peculiar to neocolonialism led to research into the economic roots of exploitation and PC!tienceo { Philosophy 1 77 into the political zmd revolutionary solutions to the overthrow of exploitation, and so to the adoption of a J\/farxisc perspective" ( r 976: 2 5 ). By and large, I agree with Copan's diagnosis, which requires a dialectic of analogical relations between the historical constructions of the Same and the new compli,mces vvith and about the Othere In this prospect, l\J.arxism achieves a radically new approach. fr does not Yl/esternize a. virgin terrain, but rather rnnfronts inattentivenesses, the supporting walls which suppose them, and assembles under the wof c.f the analogue, relations, contradictions, imaginations. In dfect, the method fesults in an original type of visibility of differences in terms of theoretical traces of taking the place o/ and representing. Alterity--be it socioeconomic or cultural-becomes through "models" £eenactable under the modalities of technical simifarities of relations between the Same and the Other. At the same time, these interpretative categories can be classified in the name of their regional context (e.g., Terray, 1969; Rey, 1973). The great originality of French Marxists and their African counterparts in the 1960s resides in this. Beginning with G. Balandier's propositions on macroperspectives in the field ( I 9 5 5 a, 19 5 5 b ), a new discourse unites what had been kept separate and opens the way to a general theory of historical and economic derivation as exemplified in the works of Osende Afana (1967), J, Snret-Canale (1958), C Meillassoux (1964, 1974), and C. Coquery-Vidrovitch (1972). The centrality of history is thus rernarkable in what Marxism expounds in African studies. In effect, the invention of an African histrncy coincides with a critical e-valuation of the history of the Same. One also observes that the possibiliry of an African history seems linked in a relation of necessity to a European questioning and redefinition of both w~hat history is not ,md vvhat it should be. For example, one notes that it is during the methodological renewal of the 1950s that Levi-Strauss, in order to celebrate the "savage mind," rdativizes the very concept of history, which as he put it, "is a disconnected whole, formed oi areas each cif 'Nhich is defined by a foeqllency of its own" (1962:340). He has since been follmved by L de Heusch and students who favor the structures of myths as pertinent loci of identity and differences (see Heusch, 1971, 19ih). The paradox becom.es dearer. The concept of "African history" marked a radical transformation of anthropological narratives. A nev, type of discourse valorizes the diachronic dimension as part of knowledge about African cultures and encourages new representations of the "native," who pre'"viously wa,, a mere object within European historicity. hs Marxist version offers the immediacy of objectivity through systems-signs of soci.oeconomic relations that permit both good pictures of local organizations o.f power and production and intercultural comparisons. By means of a similar articulation, :,trncturalisi: postulations, withmit rejecting the "new historical entity" (see, e.g., Heusch, :::971), open up areas of synchronic investigation, ~mphasizing the dialectic tension and balance between regional creatiYity and universal com:traints of the human 1T,i,1d( sec, e,g., Heusch, I 98 5 ). In sum, Tempels, The Invention of Africa Griaule, and all the apostles of African otherness have been subsumed in the Marxist project of a universal discourse of the Analogue, as witnessed to by the neatly ambiguous ideology of Presence Africaine between 1950 and 1960. We find Sartre, Fanon, Garaudy, and Soviet communist scholars speaking to, and in dialogue with Bachelard, Senghor, Cesaire, Maydieu, and Tempels. Later on, most visibly in the 1970s, structuralist methodology, in a new reflection on cultures, renewed questions of methods apropos of interpretative discourses on non-Western societies. It thus challenged an ethnohistory which tends to forget that "history is ensnared by myth which imposes its own sovereignty on kings" (Heusch, 1982:2). Structuralism proposed synchronic precepts for tabulating the forms of myths and cultures within a universal frame of relations of similarities and differences (Heusch, 1985). I cannot wholeheartedly accept Copans's analysis of the succession of methodological paradigms from Griaule to the historical materialism applied to the African context in the 1950s and 1960s nor with respect to the advent of sociology in the same period as an epistemological event which would have transformed the entire economy of African studies and the meaning of its history. Copans's analysis is slightly misleading because the critical transformation of the 1950s is essentially and directly linked to a redefinition of both the object and aim of anthropology. This crisis expressed itself in African studies in two ways. One, a critique of and improvement upon Malinowski's functionalism, which with structuralism became a whole embodying effort for reading, commenting upon, and comparing myths and cultures independently of primitivist prejudices. As a consequence, Griaule's Conversations with Ogotemmeli, and Tempels's Bantu Philosophy stand between the ghosts of Taylor, Spencer, and Frazer, on one side and the lengthy conversation which has been uniting Malinowski, Levi-Strauss, and de Heusch on the other. Strictly speaking, Griaule's or Tempels's idealism does not seem to belong to the past. Rather it still marks the oscillations of explanatory frameworks in programs for constituting or describing African forms of knowledge. The justification of Christianity seems an extreme case. It does not refer to a historical aberration but to a sociological fact: the universalization of a faith and a religious ideology appearing it1 the dispersion of both scientific and religious imaginations (see, e.g:, Bimwenyi, 198ia). Perhaps nothing has been more significant than the 1978 conference on Christianity and African Religions organized by the Roman Catholic School of Theology in Kinshasa. The Belgian scholar B. Verhaegan, who is both a Marxist and a Catholic, developed his concerns in terms of "a historical challenge": Christian religions in Africa will be marked by this triple influence: the capitalist mode of production having arrived at worldwide imperialism and having been linked to a colonial past. The question that one must pose is the Patience of Philosophy 179 folio-wing: how colonial policy first, then imperialist forces and the organic structures of independent States influenced and manipulated religion in its content as well as in its forms and structures in terms of their ow'n interests? (Verhaegen, 1979:184) To face the combined effect of these complementary factors, Verhaegen, following G. Gutierrez's theology of liberation, proposed three genres of theological discourse: a theology of modernity which will link the search for social justice to the promotion of "reason, science and progress"; a theology of charity which v,riH address the issue of social inequalities and poverty and offer radically new moral solutions; ::.nd, finally, a theology of development which will redefine modalities of development in terms of local interests (1979:188-89). Verhaegen concluded that three characteristics will mark the new African theology: it wiH be contextual, in other words, stemming from the life and culture of African people; it will be a theology of liberation because the oppression is not to be found only in cultural oppression but also in the political and economic structures; it should recognize the place of women as a vital part of the struggle for liberation and the struggle against all forms of sexism in the society and in the church. (Verhaegen, 1979:191) Throughout the following years, events and research confirmed Verhaegen's analysis. The philosophy of the Bulletin of African Theology (an ecumenical journal of the Association of African Theologians) encourages stands similar to those expounded in Verhaegen's 1979 text It is important to note a collective concern about otherness in cuh:ural and spiritual matters and the implicit integration of the "Marxist reason" in an idealist perspective on spiritual, economic, and social issues. Thus Griaule and Tempels's idealism is still operating, although in a different and discrete way. Nevertheless, it is. widespread and. efficient to the point where one might wonder if, in countries having a high percentage of Christians, such as Cameroon and Zaire, it is not a determining ideological current, at least in the short run (see, e.g., Ela, 1985). As to the second point of my slight disagreement with Copans's analysis, it bears on the importance of sociology in the reconversion of Africanism in the I 9 5 os. Let us begin by noting that the crisis in the fidd was neither original nor unique. It signified a wider malaise well-illustrated in the debate that opposed Sartre and Levi-Strauss on history as a dialectic totality, the universality of categories of reasoning, and the significance of the subject (e.g., LeviStrauss, 1962). The concepts of model and structure progressively invaded the whole field of social and human sciences, postulating both an epistemological discontirmit'f with traditional practices and a new understanding of the object of scientific inqui1-y as well as what its discourse reveals, L. Ahhusser's theory of scientific production (1965) epitomizes this awareness, The Invention of Africa Commentiqg upon the tension existing between sociology and history; E Braudel could vvrite; The vocabulary is the same, or is becoming the same, because the problematic is becon,ing increasingly the same, under the convenient heading of the cuffently dominant two words model and structure . ... In fact, whatever the cost, social science must construct a model, a general and particular explanation of social life, and substitute for a disconcerting empirical reality, a clearer image and one more susceptible to scientific application. (Braudel, 1980:73- 74) Thus, in the very center of human and social sciences, there is now affirmed a desire that in a radical manner interrogates the space of knowledge and the foundation of discourses expressing it. Levi-Strauss's critique of sociology and history as two dimensions of the same figure, which in its mode of being as wdl as in its objective and aim is not so different from the anthropological project about "primitives," convincingly affirms the importance of new epistemological determinations (see, e.g., Levi-Strauss, r 96 3 :Intro.; 1968:0verture). Following Levi-Strauss's line of reasoning, one may observe that history, as history of the Same, and its privileges are challenged. P. Veyne went further, subjecting the being of history to an evaluation and demonstrating that "history does not exist" (1984:15-30). On the other hand, he does not consecrate sociology. In the name of individual and collective identities in their differences and similarities, Veyne questioned the domain of sociological representations and the validity of its discourse: "Sociology is still at a pre-Thucydidean stage. Being history, it cannot go further than the probable, the likely" (1984:279). Comte's "sociology was a science of history 'as a whole,' a science of history; it was to establish the laws of history, like the 'law of the three estates,' which is the description of the movement of history taken as whole. But that science of history has revealed itself to be impossible" (1984:268). As a consequence, sociology no longer has an object, particularly when it claims to be autonomous from histon;. In my view, it is under this paradoxical sign of a challenged history that new horizons have opened up in African studies and account for present-day real or potential tensions, M. Herskovits's initiatives in anthropology, G. Balandier's in sociology, J. Vansina's in history, J. Coleman's search for general paradigms in political science, are contemporaneous with this critical consciousness ensuring a nevv thesis that globally negates the pertinence of the inversed figure of the Same. Concretely, they impose on the field of African studies the rejection of grids leading to pathologies of societies and, after Tempels and Griau!e, those positing and classifying pathologies of beliefs. The African project of succession also designates this same configuration as its locus of creativity. In effect, in the early 1960s, the African scholar succeeded the anthropologist, the "native" theologian replaced the missionary, and the politician took the place of the colonial commissioner. All of them find :;:easons for their vocations in the dialectic of the Same and the Patience ol Philosophy 181 Other. It is strange and significant that they tend to rationalize their missions in terms of an encounter between a narcissistic relation to the Self and the dual relation with the Other (see, e.g,, Nkrumzh, 1957; Sengho;c, 1962), Thus exegeses or commentaries on a newly discovered local rationality appear as Gestalteneinheit; that is, a self-sufficient language, accounting for its economy of being and defining itself as a historj_cal culture, becomes a frame 0£ social cooperation uniting peoples in tolerance, making events intelligible and significant, and controlling the pace of its own change (see, e.g., Abraham, 1966:215-29). In this respect, the nevv knowledge and its symbols do not destroy completely the relevance of the colonial library; nor the idealism of apostles of otherness. It has brought aboul: new standards for the coilectivi:rntion and democratization of historical reason and has reformulated residual questions concerning ideological power and scientific orthodoxy. Its best and probably excessivse illustration is the Africanization of diffusionism as actualized by Cheikh Anta Diop (e.g., 1954, 1960a, 1981). Three main initiatives combined to recapture the whole of African experience and witness to it reality·. They are the integration of Islamic sources and imaginations into the "newly expanded library," the constitution of a corpus of traditional texts, and a critical renewal of the anthropological authority. The whole conceptio11 of African history had to be defined anew on the basis of Islamic contributions (Ki-Zerbo, 1972), which affect the classical historical doctrina by bringing up new witnesses and documents. Islamic narratives enter i:rito the episteme. Some African enigmas are now examined with the aid of commentaries and descriptions by fon Hawkal (tenth century), El Bekri (eleventh century), !drisi (twelfth century), and Ibn Batuta, Ibn Khaldoun, and Maqrizi (fourteenth cemury). The sociohistorical phenomenon of "Black Islam," as studied by V. Monteil (1980), is a primary concept for some important periods of history, and the tarikhs, or chronicles, have become valued sources. Islamic sources have alvvays constituted important dimensions for the search and invention of African paradigms (see, e.g., Blyden, 1967)0 Islamic culture has powerfully contributed to the passion of alterity, particularly in West Africa, vvhere it still exposes schemas and lessons on social harmony and its philosophy (e.go, Ba, 1972; Hama, 1969; 1972; Kane, 1961). But, by and large, the Islamic discourse was until the 1960s an ideological interference within the ktema es aei embodied by the colonial library as, for example, represented ad absurdum by the life and passion of Tierno Bokar (Ba and Cardaire, 19 57; Brenner, 1984). The constitution of a corpus of A.frican traditional texts is undeniably one of the most important achievements in the field. The most impressive collection remains the series of Classiques Africains created by E. de Dampierre in Paris on the model of the Greek and Latin classics of La Collection Bude. Note that since the first years of this century, folklorists have been publishing translations of traditional narratives under the name of "oral literature" (see Scheub, 1971, 1977)" for years these collections served as professed monur! h The Invention of Africa ments to peridvilhed or marginal experiences, Frobenius's African Genesis ( r 9 3 7 ), for exam pie, contributed to a scientific curiosity by transferring narratives from their original context and language into a European language and conceptual frame. They then become formulas for a diffusionist thesis. On the '\lvholie, until the 1950s, most of the published works were based on similar transference. Narratives were submitted to a theoretical order, and rarher than accounting for their ovm being and their own meaning, they were maialy used as tools to illustrate grand theories concerning the evolution and transform2,tions of literary genres. Kagame's project of promoting an indigenous reading of traditional narratives has been-despite its internal weaknesses-one of the most serious and least extroverted approaches to African genres. By making available some ioasic texts pertinent to the hypotht,sis of Bantu ontology, the Belgian scholar, J. A. Theuws ( r 9 5 4, 1983), makes a similar contribution. Narratives presented in the truth of their language and authenticity become texts of real peoples and not merely the results of theoretical manipulations. This new perspective has been reorganizing the field for some years now. The authority of reading and classifying genres, texts, and foeratures from some kind of divine position, which does nor demand a knowledge of a specific social context, its culture, and language, is being progressively replaced by concrete questions bearing upon contextual authority and the necessity of linking narratives to their cultural and inteHectual conditions of possibiliti;. By wiy of illustration, one naturally turns to the magnificent collection of Classiques africains published first by Julliard and then by A. Col.in under the direction of E. de Dampierre. Recently, K. Anyidoho surveyed the geography of the field ( 19 8 5 ), H, Scheub evaluated the "state of the art" ( r 9 8 5 ), and S. Arnold described changing aspects of African literary studies ( 198 5 ). Examining these articles, one finds a resolute n.ev'I message: African Hterature studies is interested in knowledge and every text is worthy of being considered literature. This commitment is in itself a problem, insofar as it claims to apply to all narratives, be they in African or European languages. Diverse texts produced for differing purposes and in different economic areas are all lumped together as material for one discipline. At the rnen::y of scientific paradigms and grids, they become almost identical memories, reflecting in the same way African social relations of production, ideological signals, and cultural geographies. Intellectual histories mix with ethnographies, imaginative works in English or french with "oral narratives." The uniformizing dichotomy of modem versus traditional organizes the competing values and merits of texts. "What this sort of literary criticism does to the actual experience and meaning that the text expressed in its original cultural context does not seem to concern most students of African literature. From an anthropology redefining itself come new possibilities and questions. L. de Heasch has brought structuralism to African studies, rediscovered Frazer's universal mythemes and faced the question of the being of the Analogue. Patience of Philosophy Frazer ... curiously neglected to point out that the drama of the Passion, reen, Kted on Christian altars, is a universal theme. Christianity's greatness lies in knowing how to present the political assassination perpetrated in Judea by the Roman coloniser, as the ultimate sacrifice and in having tried to build on this schema-at the price of a metaphysical illusion-a society of peace and brotherhood. That message can never again be forgotten. Yet a blind man's sofr voice, vvhich would not have been heard outside Dagon country if Griaule had not been so attentive, also deserves to be considered as a profession of sacrificial faith, based on the hope of a more humane, more balanced world ... the sacrifice circulates "a word," destined for all, says the old Ogotemm.eli. (Heusch, 19 8 5: 206) Disciples of Ricoeur and Gadamer are also proposing ways for conciliating a critical consciousness with the authority of regional cultural texts, as in the case of Bellman's study on symbol and metaphors in Poro ritual (1984), or Tshiamalenga's philosophy of sin in the Luba tradition (1974), as well as his linguistic and anthropological analysis of the ntu vision of the human being (1973). Semiology, as an intellectual tool for examining social signs, and hermeneutics, as means and method of reading and interpreting these social signs, may indicate a future direction for African Studies. They address an apparently simple question: how can one unveil and describe African experience? Is it just a matter of the methodological association of concepts, which when applied well will reveal an empirical reality, or is it a problem concerning the explanatory principles of scientific and philosophical models? The main problem concerning the being of African discourse remains one of the transference of methods and their cultural integration in Africa. However, beyond this question lies another: how can one reconcile the demands of an identity and the credibility of a claim to knowledge with the process of refounding and reassuming an interrupted historicity within representations? l\,foreover, could not one hypothesize that, despite the cleverness of discourses and the competency of authors, they do not necessarily reveal la chose du texte, that which is out there in the African traditions, insistent and discrete, determining the traditions yet independent from them? Colonialism and its trappings, particufady applied anthropology and Christianity, tried to silence this. African discourses today, by the very epistemological distance which makes them possible, explicit, and credible as scientific or philosophical utterances, might just be commenting upon rather than unveiling la chose du texte. This notion, which belongs to hermeneutics, and ywhich according to Ricoeur's proposition calls for an obedience to the text in order to unfold its meaning, could be a key to the understanding of African gnosis. As an African responsibility, this gnosis emerged in the gradual and progressive preemi.nence of history and has marked all discourses for intellectual succession. In history, the ambition of this gnosis has, since the 1960s, been embodied in the work of such scholars as Ajayi, Ki-Zerbo, Obenga, and others. They brought into a dialogue the authority of historical methods and forms of life and societies which up to the 19 50s vvere largely considered historically The Invention of Africa mute" Against the mythologies of anthropology, rightly or wrongly, the critique historique faced ideo 1:ogies of otherness and combined with thenc:Lin synthesrn that ,;fo.imed w repn makes possible its approximate definition, always remembering of course that this nodal point of past, present and probable events does not exist as a substrawm, but only in the sense that phenomena are occurring in it ... (Levi-Strauss, 19!:lI:625-26) One could also refer to Ve,1ne's strong critique of a history of the Same that, in reality, does not exist despite its ambitions (Veyne, 1984:15-30). Most important, at least in African gnosis, are the implications of this new perspective: (a) an interrogation about the subject of discourse; (b) a reevaluation of the concept of rationality from the viewpoint of intrinsic propertiefof categories functioning in regional texts, myths and interpretations; ( c) a reconceptualization of scientific method and the relationships that "scientific knowledge" might have with other forms or t1;pes of knowledge; and ( d) a redefinition of human freedom. These are not small issues, and because of their range, structuralism, to use an unfortunate expression of 1vL P. Edmond, has been perceived as a process of de-\J{!esternizing scientific knowledge (Edmond, 1965:43-44). Let me be frank: twenty years of careful study of structuralism have convinced me that although there is an impressive body of good and comprehensive analyses on structuralism in which one finds stimulating and highly technical criticisms (e.g., Beiddman, 1966; Turner, 1969) and philoConclusion 199 sophical challenges (e.g., Ricoeur, 1969), a great number of criticisms of Levi-Strauss are consciously or unconsciously ideological, even, 1 would say, raciaHy motivated. They can often be reduced to the two follov:ring statements: Is not strncturaHsm a Jewish enterprise against the achievements of the Christian West? And, as one of my European students put it, forgetting my origin: "Levi-Strauss does them too much honor." Concerning the methodology of describing African cultural dynamics, the difficult exchange that exists nowadays between J. Vansina and L de Heusch, T. Obenga and his opponents, P. I-Iountondji and his critics, is a sign of the organic richness of discourses focusing on the individuality of norms, rules, and systems. These discourses show the perilous path of the future. On the other hand, they point to the delicate validity of patient translations and interpretations of regional cultural economies, such as the work of Lienhardt (1961), Buakasa (1973), Jackson (1982), and Izard (1985), This orientation is revealed most explicitly in Bird and Karp's collection of specialized studies, Explorations in African Systems of Thought (1980), and in Beidelman's study on Kaguru modes of thought (1986). The domain of a universal language (langage) or megarationality has been replaced by the criterion of experiential authoriLJ' "inventing" itself as translation and exegesis of institutional and well-delineated languages (langues) founded by concrete performances (paroles), ,What one gets is thus a decisive critique of traditional methods of correlating the Same to the Other, In JB. Bames's words, these enterprises from within indicate that "making a demarcation in actors' own terms is usduli for explanatory purposes. Such a demarcation is part of the actors' perception of the situation; and action is inteBigible only as a response to that perception . , . Making a demarcation by external standards, on the other hand, is useless for explanatory purposes ... " (1974:100). It is obvious that such a method should define itseH as a critical system of making statements, which could only partially unveil the social and cultural archives of a society. \Vhat then should we do with the problem of a transhistoric thought? From the rhetorical margins of history, i.t opens upon a paradox: something like the pure reflection of consciousness in a pure language, It enlarges and universalizes regional archives and brings them into contact with the analyst's mind, thus inventing in a dynamic manner both understanding and hi.story. It is useful "for history to move m;vay from us in time or for us to move away from it in thought, for it to cease to be intemalizable and to lose its intelligibility, a spurious intelligibiliry attaching to a temporary internaliiy" (Levi-Strauss, 1966:225). This does not constitute the negation of the truth of social forms as expressed and generated by the dialectic between Leben (living and sharing with others) and Gemeinsamkeit (a permeating community). On the contrary, a permanent recapitulation of this dialectic should remain as an endless task of reading, commenting upon the permanent production of cultural legends and "une parn!e pour-soi." Foucault once said that he deprived "1:he sovereignty of the subject of the 200 Conclusion exclusive and instant right to discourse." That is good nev,rs. I believe that the geography of .African gnosis also points out the passion of a subject-object who refuses to vanish. He or she has gone from the situation in which he or she was perceived as a simple functional object to the freedom of thinking of himself or herself as the starting point of an absolute discourse. Xt has also become obvious, even for this subject, that the space interrogated by the series of explorations in African indigenous systems of thought is not a void. APPENDIX ETHIOPilt.N SOURCES OF KJ:\~CPXTLJEDGE "If Abyssinia had been a colony; for example, the most ardent believer in the preservation of native culture would not have advocz,ted the recreation of -che pre-Christian religion" wrote L P. Mair (Malinowski :ind others, 1938:4). ln the lvfarxist Ethiopia of today, a Canadian scholar, C Sumner, has made a major contribution to the search for a new outlook on "African philosophy." He thinks that "there is an urgent need that philosophy, taught in fahiopic: at a university level, should not be entirely alien, but integrate values found at home, in the fertile riative ground" (Sumner, 1974:3). He has so far made available the following major sources. (1) The Bool~ o/ the Wise Philosophers has been known since 1875 thanks to C. R Cornill (Das Buch der Weisen Phi!osophen nach clern Aethiopischen untersucht, Leipzig) and A. DiHmann ( Chrestomathia Aethio;/Jica, 1950, Berli.n)" his an anthology of sayings, most attributed to such philosophers as Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and Galen, "The rnajority of the sayings vvere exhortations and advice, ofren ack~ressed by a wise man to a disciple or to his son" (Sumner, 1974:4), The text used is a Gt:ez translation from an Arabic original compi.led between 1510 and r 5 22 by Abba lviikael, an Arabic-speaking Egyptian. It ls profoundly marked by Greek and Christi: m influences, as shown in references tv Socrates's lifo and to platonic philosophy and in quotations of early church fathers such as Gregory andl JBasiL (2) The Treatise of Zlir'.a Yacob and of Walda Heywat. The corpi1s of these seventeenth,-century texts was established for the first time in 1904 by E. Littman (Philosophia Abessini, Corpus Scriptorum Christim.oruvn OrientaEium 18, (1):Paris). Sumner's edition (1;?J76, 1978) is the first complete English version (1976:3-59). The vmrk comprises tvvo hatatas, aut0- biographical mechtations, The Zar'a Yacob (seed of Jacob) is divickd into twenty-five chapters be;;iring on thi:: author's life, the eternity of God, division among believers, the meaning of faith and prayer, the Jaw of God and i:he hvv of man, Mosaic law and Mohammed's mechtmion, physical and spiritual work, marriage, and the nature of knowkdge, Composed of thirty-:5.ve brief chapters, the Treatise of Walda Heywat (son of life) exar1ines such topics a;:; creation, knoc,,1ledge, faith, the nature of the wul, law an.cl judgf.mem, social life, the use ot love, virtues and human -weaknesses, echication, tirfa:\ and culture. lin his 1904 edition, Littmann noted the int:c:llectualp •mver ·.J.ncol riginality of these works. 20:;: 202. Appendix \l(/hile the greater part of Ethiopian literature is translated from foreign l.angrnages, these [WO books written by Abyssiinians are in1bu,~cl with their ovvn native ch,;,racter ... 1-Iow;cveIr ,w ould say that these flowers could not grow solely from the Ethiopian ground, unless they had been irrigated by external waters. (In Sufnner, 1976:63) In 1916, Carlo Conti Rossini hypothesized that the t!'eatises were of Emopean origin and suggested the author might have been Giusto D'Urbino, an hali:m missionary. Eventually, the tv10 hatatas came to be considered ninet, ernth-ce!ltury Italian works. Sumner hz.8 ·1Norked to prove the contraq and to reestablish the Ethiopian origin of the rexts (Sumner, 1976:250--75). Hov.rever, in his extensive analysis, Sumner comp2,n,s Zar-a Yacob to Mani, Luther, Herbert of Cherbury, Rene Descartes and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1978: 6 5-73). He thinks that "many of the ideas developed! in the Hatata are similar 1:0, and im some instances identical with, the Tractatus de Veritate and the Discours sur la methode. Bm the convergence would not apply beyond the logical level of a common rationalistic approach and or epistemological investigations" ( r 9 7 8: t, r ). (3) The Life and Maxims of Skandes is an Ethiopic version of the wellknown text of Secund11s, whose roots go back to i:he first centuries of the Roman EmpirL It has survived in two lineages: 'Jlfestem (Greek and Latin) and Eastern (Syriac, Arabic, and Ethiopic). Sumner reproduces the edition established by Bachmann: Das Leben und die Sentenzen des Philosophen Sewndus das Schweigsamen (1887, Halle\ This Geez version bdongs to the L':'34-1468 literary period and is a translation of an earlier Arabic text. The theme of the book is a question: what is the relation between a -woman's will :md her instinctive tendencies? Et is also a commentary on the shocking maxim that aH wornen are prostitutes. According to Sumner, rhe Ethiopian version is, from a literary viewpoint, original. "The translator very often departs from the A.rabic original. He both subtracts and adds" (1981:437). Sumner is preparing two other volumes for publication: The Fisalgwos 2nd Basic Ethiopian Philosophical Texts. Greeting the publication of The Boo.k of the Wise Philosophers, L. Nusco, of the then Haile Selassie I University, remarked th2t the book "is not a work of philosophy in the technical sense of the word,"' adding that "such a classification would cause the indignation of aE professional philosophers" (Sumner, I97"1-l- fr:. his eval1uation of the 1976 Addis Ababa Seminar on African philosophy, Van Parys asked whether or not these treatises are really Ethiopian, since at lea.st the first and the third are transladons. }-Hs answer is prudent: they are original and creativdy Ethiopian, but apart from the second, they are not really criticaL "It i.s in the comparisons bet\veen Arab and Greek on one hand and Ethiopian on the other that is found Ethiopian originality. I-fowever none of these works shavv the critical spirit that characterizes modern thinking" (Van Panis, 1978:65). This is possibly a matter of opini,on. The body of ancient Ethiopian texts Ethiopian Sources does not conceal its sources. Nevertheless one cannot ignore that some of them, s11ch as the books or Zar'a Yacob and \Valda Heywat, witness to a regional inspiration. fa any case, all these texts are somehow "subjects" commencing upon themselves and their restlessness, The fact is that, as in the case of most intellectual contributions, there is a mystery on two sides: the genealogical reciprocity existing between the Ethiopian versions and their historical references, and, on the other hand, the privileges of their own textuality, In a paper focusing on the ethical aspects of this literature, Sumner has emphasized the complementarity of these two aspects: If W'io consider together the t'JVO expressions of Ethiopian Philosophy: translation, adaptation and personal reflection, popular-traditional wisdom and rationalism O •• we come to a fevv conclusions which can be summarized under four headings: centrality, comprehensiveness, richness, theological basis. (Sumner, 1983:99) For Sumner, the notion of centrality is linked to that of moral importance or prevalence that "characterizes all types of Ethiopian thought:' That of comprehensiveness implies that "aH aspects, objective and subjective, proximate and ultimate, are taken into consideration in the assessment of the norms of morality." The concept of richness is a theoretical image expressing connotations and implications stemming from "the key word of 'heart,' the radiating polarity of 'conscience'" in the texi:s. Finally, there is the theological basis, which is radically anthropocentric. About the sixteenth-century Book of the Wise Philosophers and the seventeenth-century philosophical treatises of Zar'a Yacob and his disciple Walda Heywat, Sumner proposes hypotheses that clearly discriminate them from the tradition that produced them: Both are opposed to any kind of religious revelation, and hence are not Christian in any way; they are, in that sense, explicitly anti-Christian. And yet their rationalism led them to a dear, pure, abstract theism. l~or the natural light of reason, however opposed to any revealed positive light, is nonetheless a penetration of the divine into the creatural. (Sumner, r 9 8 3: r oo) Thus, one can. provisionally note that textual deviations mean what they silently or explicitly negate: the intellectual locus of their possibility, .At the same time and more important, by their very presence they also indicate a remarkable instance of a culturally regional authoriry in terms of creativity. BIBLIOGRAPHY A.BANDA NDEGUE, M. J. (1970). De let negritude au negrisme. Yaounde: Cle. ABLEGMAGNON, F.NL (1957). "Du 'temps' clans la culture Ewe." Presence Africaine nos. u,-15: 222-32. ---. (1958). "Personne, tradition et culture." In Aspects de la culture noire. Paris: Fayard. ---. (1960). "L'Afrique noire: La Metaphysique, l'ethique, !'evolution actuelle." Comprendre nos. 21-22:74-82... ----. (1962). "Totafaes et systemes clans les societes d'Afrique noire." Pr,esence Africaine no. 41:13-22. ABR..'I.HAMw, . E. (1966). The Mind of Africa. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. ADELE JINADU, L. (1976). "The Moral Dimensions of the Political Thought of Frantz Fanon." Second Order 5 (1). ADOTEVI, s. (1972). Negritude et negrologues. Paris: Pion. ADOUKOUNOU, B. (1981). Jalons pour une theologie africaine. 2 vols. Paris: LethieHeux. At'ANA, o. ([1967] 1976). L'Economie de l'ouest africain. Paris: Maspero. AGASSI, J. (1963). Towards an Historiography of Science. The Hague: North Holland Publishing Company. AGossou, J.M. (1972). Gbet'o et Gbedo'to. Paris: Beauchesne. ---. (1977). "Pour un Christianisme africain." Cahiers des religions africaines II, 21-22, I. AGUOLU, c. (1975). "John Dewey's Democratic Conception and its Implication for Developing Nations." Second Order 4 (2). AHIDJO, A. (1964). Contribution a la construction nationale. Paris: Presence Africaim:. ---. (1969). Nation et developpeinent dans /'unite. Paris: Presence Africaine. AJAYI, J. F. A. (1969). "Colonialism: An Episode in African History." In Colonialism in Africa 1870-1960, L. H. Gann and P. Duignan, eds. vol. 1 of The History and Politics of Colonialism. Cambridge: Cambridge Universiry Press. AJAYI, J. F. A. and CROWDER, M. (1972). History of West Africa. London: Longmans. AJISAFE, iL K. (192"4). The Laws and Customs of the Yoruba People. AKE, c. (1979). Social Science as Imperiaiism: The Theory of Political Development. Lagos: University of lbadan Press. ALUER, R. (1925). La Psychologie de la Conversion cheiz;l es Peuples non-civilises. Paris: Payot. ALMOND, A. G., and COLEMAN, J. s., eds. (r960). The Politics of Developing Areas. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ALTHUSSER, L. (1965). Pour Marx. Paris: Maspero. (For Marx, New York: Pantheon). AMIN, s. (1964). Neo-Colonialism in West Africa. Harmondsworth: Penguin. ---. (1965). Trois experiences afT"icaineds e developpement: le Mali, la Guinee et le Ghana. Paris: Presses universitaires de France ----. (1967). Le Developpement du capitalisme en Cote d'Ivoire. Paris: Editions de Minuit. -·--·. (1969). Le Monde d'affaires senegalaises. Paris: Editions de 1viinuit. ---. (1973). Le Developpement inegal. Essai sur les formations sociales du capitalisrne peripherique. Paris: Editions de Ivhrmit. (Unequal Development. New York: Monthly Review Press) .. 205 206 Bibliography ----. (197"1.). L'Accuw1u!atio"1 a l'echeile moncliale. Paris: Anthropos. (Accumulation on a World Scale: A Critique of the Theory of Underdevelopment, New York: 11.fonthly Review, 1974). ----. (1979). Classe et nation dans l'histoire et la crise contemporaine. Paris: Editions de Nlinuit. AMIN, s., and COQUERY-VrnROVITCH, c. (1969). Histoire economique du Car.go, 1880-I968. Paris: Anthropos. AMSELLE, J. L (1979). Le Sauvage a la mode. Paris: Le Sycamore. ANYIIJOI-m, K. ( I 9 8 5 ). "The Present State of African Oral Literamre Studies." In Africar. Literature Studies. The Present State/L'Etat Present, Arnold, S., ed. ',Xi'ashington, D.c.: Three Continents Press. APOLUNAIRE, G. (1913). Les Peintres cubistes. Paris: E. Figuiere. APPIAH-KUB!, K, and TORRES, s. (1977). African Theology en Route. l'•Tew York: Orbis. ARENDT, H. (1968). Imperialism: Part Two of the Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ARINZJE, F. A. (I970). Sacrifice in Ibo Religion. lbadan. ARNOLD, s. (I985). "African Literary Studies: The En:ergence of a new discipline." In African Literature Studies. The Present State/L'Etat Present, S. Arnold, ed. 'JVashington, D.C.: Three Continents Press. ARRIGHI, R. (1979). Liberation ou Adaptation. La Theologie africaine s'interroge. Le Co!loque d'Accra. Paris: L'Harmattan. ASAD, T., ed. (1973). Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter. New York: Humanities Press. ASHBY, E. (1966). Universities: British, Indian, African: A Study in the Ecology of Higher Education. London: Weidenfeid & Nicolson. ASTIER-LOUTFI, M. (1971). Litterature et colonialisme: L'Expansion coloniale vue dans ta litterature fram;aise. Paris: Mouton. ATAL, D. (1972). Structures et signification des cinq premiers versets de l'hymne johannique au. logos. Louvain-Paris: Beatrice-Nauwelaerts. ATANGANA, N. (1971). Travail et developpement. Yaounde: Cle. AUGE, M. (1979). Symbole, fonction, histoire. Les interrogations de l'anthropologie. Pari.s: Hachette. AWOLOWO, o. (1947). Path to Nigerian Freedom. London: Faber and Faber. ---. (1968). The Peoples' Republic. foadan: Oxford University Press. AYANDELE, E. (1966). The Missionary Impact on Modern .Nigeria, r842-1914. London: Longman. AZIKI\VE, N. (1937). Renascent Africa. New ed. 1969. London: Cass. --. (1961). Zik: A Selection from the Speeches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. AZOMBO-MEN~A, s. M., and ANOBO, K. (1978). Les Philosophes afrfcains par les textes. Paris: Nathan. BA, A. H. (1972). Aspects de la civilisation africaine. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1976). Jesus vu par un musulrnan. Dakar-Abidjan: Nouvelles editions africaines. BA, A. H., and CARDAHllE, IvI. (1957). Tierno Bokar, le sage de Bandiagara. Paris: Pn§sence Africaine. BA, A. H., and DIETERLEN, G. (1961). Koumen. Texte initiatique des pasteurs Peul. Paris: Mourcn. BADIAN, s. (1964). Les Dirigeants a/ricains /ace a leur peuple. Paris: Maspero. BAETA, c. G., ed. (1968). Christianity in Tropical Africa. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BAHOKEN, J. c. (1967). Clairie:-es metaphysiques africaines. Essai sur la philosophie et la religion chez les Bantu du Sud-Cameroun. Paris: Presence Africaine. Bibiiography 207 BAUWCH, P. (1971). Le Tiers Monde dans /'impasse. Paris: GaUimard. BAL, w. (1963). Le Royaume du Congo aux xve et XVJe siecles. Documents d'histoire. Leopoldville (Kinshasa): Insdtut National d'Etudes Politiques. BALANmER, G. (1955a). Sociologie des Brazzavilles noirs. Paris: A. Colin. ---. ( 19 5 5 b ). Sociologie actuel!e de l'Afrique noire. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. --. (1957). Afrique ambigue'. Paris: Pion. ---. (1967). Anthropologie politique. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. BAMUINIKKLE, s. (1971). La Mort et l'au-dela chez les Baluba du Kasai. Lubumbashi: CEPSi BARAN, iP. (1957) The Political Economy of Growth. New York: Modern Reader Paperbacks. BARL!'.Y, N. (1984). Adventures in a Mud Hut. New York: The Vanguard Press. BARNES, B. (1974). Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. BA&c"IBTT, D. B. (1968). Schism and Renewal in Africa. Nairobi: Oxford University Press. ---. (1970). "A.D. 2000-350 Million Christians in Africa." International Review of Missions, 59 (233l:39-54. ---, ed. (1974). l'l.frican Initiatives in Religion. Nairobi: East African Publishing House. BARIHES, R. (1979). The Eiflel Tower and Other Mythologies. New York: Hill and Wang. BASSE, E.C. (1977). "hineraire de Presence Africaine: Probleme de l'eglise en Afrique." Cahiers des religions africaines II, 2.1-22, I. BASTIDE, R. (1961). "Variations sur la negritude." Presence fl{ricaine no, 36. ---. (1967). "Color, Racism, and Christianity." Daedalus 96 (2):312.-27. BATTLE, v. M., and LYONS, c. H. eds. (1970), Essays in the History of African Education. New York: Teachers College Press. BAUDRILLARD, J. (r972). Pour une critique de Z'economie politique du signe. Paris: Gallimard. ---. (1977). Le Mirroir de la production: ou L'Illusion critique du materialisme historique. Tournai: Casterman. (The Mirror of Production. St. Louis: Telos, 1975). BAYART, J. F. ( 1979 ). L'Etat au Cameroun. Paris: Presse de la Fondation Nationale des Sciences Pohtiques. ---. (1983). "La Revanche des societes africaines." Politique africaine 1:95-127. BEATTIE, J. (1973). "Understanding Trnditional African Religion: A Con1ment on Horton." Second Order 2, (2). BEIDELMAN, T. o. (1966). "Swazi Royal Ritual." Africa 34 (4l:373-405. ---. (1986). Moral Imagination in Kaguru NI.odes of Thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. BEIER, u., ed. (1966). The Origin of Life and Death. London: Heinemann. BELL!v1AN, B. L (1984). The Language of Secrecy: Symbols and Metaphors in Poro Ritual. Nevv Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. BERGH, P. VAN DEN. (1973). Power and Privilege at an African University. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. BETTS, R. P. (1975). The False Dawn: European Imperialism in the XD( th Century. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. BIGO, P. (1974). L'Eglise et la revolution du tiers monde. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. BliMVJENYI, o. (1968). "Le Muntu a la lumiere de ses croyances en 1'au-de1a,"C ahiers des religions africaines 8:137-51; 9 (1971):59-II2 .. 208 Bibliography (1981a). Discours theologique negro 0 Africain. Problemes de fondements. Paris: Presence Africaine. ----. (19816). "L'Inculturation en Afrique et attitude des agents de l'evangelisation." Aspects du catholicisnie au Zaire. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. BINSBERGEN, w. M. J. VAN. (1981). Religious Change in Zambia: Exploratory Studies. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul BINSBERGEN, w. M. J. VAN, and SCHOFFELEERS, M., eds. (193 5). Theoretical Explorations in African Religion. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. BIRD, c. s. and KARP, L, eds. (1980), Explorations in African Systems of Thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. BJORNSON, R., and MOWOE, L J., eds. (1986). Africa and the Wiest. New York: Greenwood Press. BLACK, M., (1962). Models and Meta/Jhors. J\[evv York, !thaca: Cornell University Press. BLAIR, D. (1976). African Literature in French. Cambridge: Cambridge Universily P'feSS. BLOCH, M., (1961). Feudal Society. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. BLYDEN, E. w. (1862). Liberia's Offering, New York, 1862. (LO) It contains the following texts: (1) "Hope for Africa," 5-28. (2) "A Vindication of the African Race," (Liberia, 18 57):31-64. (3) "The Call of Providence to the Descendants of Africa in America," 67-91. (4) "Inaugural Address at the Inauguration of Liberia College," 95-123. (5) "Eulogy on Rev. John Day," 127-149. (6) "A Chapter in the History of the African Slave-Trade," 153-167. (7) "A Note to Benjamin Coates on 'The Colonization and Abolition Movements'," 169-181. ---. (1869a). Liberia: Past, Present, and Future. (LPPF) Washington. ---. (1869b). The Negro in Ancient History. (NAH) Washington. ---. (1888). Christianity, Islam and The Negro Race. (CINR) London. New edition, 1967, at Edinburgh University Press. --. (1903). Africa and Africans. (AA) London. -· --. (1978). Selected letters o/ Edward Wilmot Blyden, (LET) ed., Hollis R. Lynch. New York: KTO Press. BODUNRKN, P. o. (1975a). "Values and Objectivity in the Social Sciences." Thought and Practice 2, (1). ---. (1975b). "The Alogicality of Immortality." Second Order 4 (2). ---. (1978). "Witchcraft, Magic and E.S.P." Second Order 7 (1 and 2). BOELAERT, E. (1946). "La Philosophie bantoue selon le R. P. Placide Tempels." Aequatoria 9:81-90. iBOESAK, A. A. (1977). Farewell to Innocence: A Socio-Ethical Study on Black Theology and Black Power. New York: Orbis. ---. (1984a). Blac.k and Reformed: Apartheid, Liberation and the Calvinist Tradition. New· York: Orbis. ---. (1984b). Walking on Thorns: The Call to Christian Obedience. Grand Rapids: W, B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. BOHANNAN, P. ([1953] 1980). "Concepts of Time among the Tiv of Nigeria." In Myth and Cosmos, Middleton, J., ed. Austin: University of Texas Press. BONTE, P. (15176). "Marxisme et anthropologie: Les Malheurs d'un empiriste." L'Homme 16 (4):129-36. BONTINCK, F. (1980). "Mfumu Paul Panda Farnana (1888-1930) Premier (?) nationaliste congolais." In Africa's Dependence and the Remedies, V. Y. Mudimbe, ed. Paris: Berger-Levrault. Bibliography 209 BOOTH, N. s., ed. (1977). Af.-,-icanR eligions: A Symposium. £\TewY ork: Nok. BOURDIEU, P. (1973). "The Three Forms of Theoretical Knowledge." Social Science Information 14 (6):19-,1-7. BOURGEOIS, A. (1971). La Grece antique devant la negritude. Paris: Presence Africaine. BRAUDEL, F., (1980). On History. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. BRELSFORD, v. (1935). Primitive Philosophy. London: J. Bale ---. (1938). "The Philosophy of the Savage." Nada, 15. BRENNER, L. (1984). West African Sufi: The Religious Heritage and Spiritual Search of Cerna Bokar Saalil Taal. Berkeley/Los Angeles: Universit"f of California Press. BROWN, R., ed. (1973). Knowledge, Education and Cultural Change. London: Tavistock. BRUNSCHWIG, H. (1963). L'Avenement de l'Afrique noire du XJXe siecle a nos jours. Paris: A. Colin. BUAKASA, T. K. M. (1973). L'Irnpense du discours. Kindoki et nkisi en pays Kongo du Zaire. Kinshasa: Presses Universitaires clu Zaire. ---. (1978). "Les Sciences de l'occident: Pour quoi faire?" Philosophie et liberation, Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. BUHLMANN, w. (1978). The Coming of the Third Church. New York: Orbis. ---. (1979). The Missions on Trial. New York: Orbis. ---. (1980). All Have the Same God. New York: Orbis. ---. (1982). The Chosen Peoples. New York: Orbis. BUJO, B. (1975). Morale africaine et foi chretienne. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. BURIEAU, R. (1962). "Les Missions en question. La Conversion des cultures." Christus no. 9:34. BUSIA, IC H. (1951). The Position of the Chief in the Modern Political System of Ashanti. London. ---. (1962). The Challenge of Africa. London: Pall Mall. CALVET, J. L. (1972). Linguistique et colonialisme. Paris. CASTERAN, c., and LANGELUER, J.P. (1978). L'Afrique deboussolee. Paris: Pion. CENDRARS, B. (1921). Anthologie negre. New ed. 1972. Paris: Buchet-Chastel. CERM. (1969). Sur le mode de production asiatique. Paris: Editions Sociales. ---. (1973). Sur Jes societes precapitalistes. Textes choisis de Marx, Engels, Lenine. Paris: Editions Sociales. CERTEAU, M. DE. (1969). L'Etranger ou l'Union dans la difference. Paris: Desdee de Brouwer. ---. (1984). The Practice of Everyday Life. Los Angeles: University of California Press. CESAHIB, A. (1950). Discours sur le colonialisme. Paris: Presence Africaine (Discourse on Colonialism. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1972). ---. (1956). Lettre a Maurice Thorez. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1959-60). "La Pensee Politique de Sekou Toure." Presence Africaine no. 29. CHENU, B. (1977). Dieu est noir. Paris: Le Centurion. CHILCOTE, R.H. (1981). Dependency and Marxism. Boulder: '\Y/estview Press. CHKNW"EIZU, JEMIE, MADUBUIKE. (1983). Toward the Decolonization of African Literature. 'Xlashington, D.c.: Howard University Press. CHIPENDA, J.B. (1977). "Theological Options in Africa Today." ln African Theology En Route, Appiah-Ku.bi and Torres, eds. New York: Orbis. CHRISTOPHER, A. J. (1984). Colonial Africa. Totowa, New Jersey: Barnes and Noble. CLARENCE-SMITH, w. G. (1977). "For Brau.de!: A Note on the Ecole des Annales and the Historiography of Africa." History in Africa 4:275-81. ----. (1985). The Third Portuguese Empire 1825-1975: A Study in Economic Imperialism. Manchester: Manchester University Press. 210 Bibliography CLARK, G, (1936). The Balance Sheets of Imperialism. New York: Columbia University Press. CL~FFORD, J. (1983). "On Ethnographic Authority." Representations r (2.). COHEN, R. (1977). "Oedipus Rex and Regina: the Queen Mother in Africa." Africa 47 (:u:). COLEMAN, J. s. (1956). Togoland. l'-Jew York: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. ---. (I965). Nigeria: Background to Nationalism. Berkeley: University of California Friess. COLEMAN, J. s., and ALMOND, G. A., eds. (1960). The Politics of the Developing Areas. Princeton: Princeton Universii)' Press. COLEMAN, J. s., and HALISI, c. R. D. (1983). "American Political Science and Tropical Africa: Universalism vs. Relativism." African Studies Review 26 (3/4):25-62. COLEMAN, J. s., and ROSBERG, c. G. Jr., eds. (1964). Political Parties and National Integration in Tropical Africa. Berkeley: University of California Press. COLLINGWOOD, R. G. (1946). The Idea of History. London: Oxford University Press. COPANS, J. (:r97rn). "Pour une histoi.re et une sociologie des etudes africaines." Cahiers d'etudes africaines II, 43. Repr. as "African Studies: A Periodization." In African Social Studies: A Radical Reader, P. Gutkin cl and P. Waterman, eds. (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978). ---. (1971b). Critiques et politiques de l'anthropologie. Paris: Maspero. ---. (1974). Anthropologie et imperialisme. Paris: Maspero. COQUERY-VIJDROVITCH, Co (1969a). "Anthropologie politique et histoire de i'Afrique." Annales 24 (1):142-63. ---. (r969b). "Recherches sur un mode de production africaine." La Pensee, no. 144:61-78. ---. (1972). Le Congo au temps des grandes compagnies concessionaires. Paris: Mouton. ---. (I980). "Analyse historique et concept de mode de production clans les societes capitalistes." L'Homme et la societe 5 5-5 8, 104-44. ---. (1984\ "Reflexions d'historienne." In Mode of Production: The Challenge of Africa, B. Jevvsiewicki and J. Letourneau, eds. Ste-Foy, Canada: Safi. ---, and MONIOT, H. (1974). L'Afrique noire de z8oo a nos jours. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. CORDELL, D. D. (1985). Dar al-Kuti and the Last Years of the Trans-Saharan Slave Trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. CORREIA, J. A. (1925). "Vocables philosophiques et religieux des peuples foo." Bibliotheca Ethnologica Linguistica Africana r. cosMA0, v. (:u:979). Changer le monde. Paris: Cerf. COUNT, E. w., ed. (1950). This is Race: An Anthology Selected from the International Literature on the Races of Man. Nev11 York: Schuman. CR.I\.HAY, F. (1965), "Le Dfo::ilbge conceptuel: conditions d'1.me philosophie bantoue." Diogene, 52, 61-84. cuRnN, P. D. (1961). "'The \White Man's Grave': Image and Reality, 1780-1850." Journal of British Studies I :94-1 ro. ---. (1964). Africa Remembered: Narratives by West Africans from the Era of the Slave Trade. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. ---. (1965). The Image of Africa: British Thought and Action 1780-1850. Madison: Universiry of \lf/isconsin Press. DAMANN, E. (1964). Les Religions d'Afriqtte noire. Paris: Payot. DAMAS, L. G. (1979) "The Last Public Statement of L.-G. Damas." Hommage Posthume a L. G. Damas. Paris: Presence Africaine. DANQUAH, J. B. (1928). Akan Laws and Customs. ---. (1968) The Akan Doctrine of God. London: Cass. Bibliography DAVIDSON, B. (1959). 'The Lost Cities of Africa. Boston: Little, Brown. --. (1970). The African Genius. Boston: Little, Brown. DECRAEMER, w. (J[977). The ]amaa and the Church. Oxford: Clarendon. DELAFOSSEM, . (1922). L'Ame negre. Paris: PayoL ---. (I927). Les Negres. Paris: Rieder. DELANGE, J. (1967). Arts et peufJles d'Afrique noire. Paris: Gallimard. DJELAVXGNETRIB. ,( 1962). L'rlfrique noire et son des.tir.,.P aris: GaHimard. 211 DELJEUZEG, ., and GUA'TTARI, E (1972). L'imti-Oedipe. Paris: Editions de Minuit. DJELHAISEc,. (1909). "Les ldees religieuses et philosophiques des Waregas." Mouvement geographique 29. DELOBSON, D. (193:z.). L'Empire du Mogho-Naba. Paris: Domat Montchretien. ·---. (1934). Les Secrets des sorciers noirs. Paris. DENG, F. NI. (1972.). The Dinka of the Sudan. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. DEPESTRE, R. (1980). Bonjour et adieu a la negritude. Paris: Laffont. DESCHAMPS, H. (1971). Histoire de la traite des noirs de l'antiquite a nos fours. Paris: Fayard. ---. (1954), Les Religions de l'_Afrique noire. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. DESMOND CLARK, J., and BRANDT, s. A., eds. (1984). From Hunters to Farmers. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California P£ess. DHOQUOIS, G. (1966). "Le Mode de production asiatique." Cahiers internationaux de socioiogie 41, 83-92. DIA, M. (1957). L'Economie africaine. Paris: Presses 1.miversit:1ires de France. ---. (1960). Nations afi·icaines et solidarite mondiale. Paris: Pm,ses universitaires de France. ---. (1975). Islam, societes africaines et culture industrielle. Dakar: NEA. ---. (1977-1981), Essais sur nslam . .3 vols. I. Islam et humanisme. 2, Socio- Anthropologie de l'Idam. 3. Islam et ci1>ilis,1tionsn egro-africaines. Dakar: Nouvelles editions africaines. . · .· DIAGNE, M. (1976). "Paulin J. Hountondji. ·mi. La Psychanalyse de ia conscience erhno-phi!osophique." Psychopathologie Af·ricafne, 3, XII. mAGNE, P. (1967). Pouvoir politique (1954). Le Culte de Zie. Dakar: Han. ---. (1965). Le Separatisme religieux en Afrique noire. Paris: Presses umver·· sitaires de France. ---. (1968a). Les Dieux de l'Afrique. Paris: Geuthner. ---. (19686). L'Image du monde bete. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. HOLDEN, E. (1967). Blyden of Liberia. New York: Vantage. HOLLIS, lVL (1913I). "The Limits of lrrationaliry." In Rationality, B. R. ',Xlilson, ed. Oxford: Basil BlacbveH. HORTON, R. (196r). "Destiny and the Unconscious in West Africa." Africa 3I (2):no-16. ---. (1972). "Spiritual Beings and Elementary Particles." Second Order 1 (1). ---. (1976). "Traditional Thought and the Emerging African Philosophy Department: A Comment on the Current Debateo" Second Order 6 (1). ---. (1981). "African Traditional Thought and Western Science." In Rationality, B. R. Wilson, ed, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. HOUNTONDJI, P. (1970). "Rem.arques sur la philosophie africaine cont,emporaine." Diogene no. 71. ---. (1977). Sur la philosophie alricaine. Paris: Maspero (African Philosophy: JVJ.ytha nd Reality. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 198 3 ). ----. (1980). "Distances." Recherche, pedagogie et culture 49, 27-33. ----. (1981). "Que peut la philosophie?" Presence Africaine no, II9:47-71. •---. (1982). "Occidentalisrne, Elitisme: rep:::mse a deux critiques." Recherchc, pedagogie et culture 9, 5 6. ---·. (1983). "Reason and Tradition." In Philosophy and Cultures, 0. Oruka, edo l'fairobi: Bookvvise Limited. H0\1'/LJETT, J. (1974). "La Philosophie africaine en question." Presence Africaine 91:14-250 IDONjiBOYE, D. :E. (1973). "The Concept of 'Spirit' in African Metaphysics." Second Order 2 (r). mowu, E. B. (I962). Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief London: Longmans. -·--·. (1965). Towards an Indigenous Church. Oxford University Press. ----. (1975). African Traditional Religion: A Definition. New· York: Orbis. IL!FFJE, J. (198 3 ). The Emergence of African CafJitalism. M.inneapolis: University of Nlinnesota P.ress. ISICHEI, P. A. c. (1975). "T,,1voR ~rspecfr,es to the Past: History and Myth." Second Order 4 (2.). IYEKI, J. F. (1956). Essai de psychologie du primitif. Leopoldville (Kinshasa): Editions de la Voix du Congol.ais. - IZARD, M. (1985). Gens du pouvoir. Gens de la terre. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bibliography 217 JACKSON, M. (1982). Allegories of the Wilderness: Ethics and Ambiguity in Kuranko Narratives. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. JAHN, J. (1961). Muntu: An Outline of the New African Culture. New York: Grove Press. ---: (1965). Die Neoafrikanische Literatur. Gesamtbibliographie van den Anfiingen bis zur Oegenwart. Dusseldorf-Ki:iln: Eugen Diederichs. ---. (1968); A Histdifef Neo-African Literature. London: Faber and Faber. JEANS ON, F. (1949). '~Sarti<:e t le monde noir." Presence Africaine no. 7. JEWSIEWICKI, B. {19,8'ii);.' li~ffiistoire en Afrique ou Le Commerce des idees usagees." In Les Faux'· · s de l'Afrique, A. Schwarz, ed. Quebec: Presses de l'Universi --. (198:r):O Central Stewart 'e --. (198;Y-" veloping JEWSIEWICKI, B.; lenge of JEWSIEWICKI, B,; Hills: Sag JORDAN, W. D. ( 1550-18 JULES-ROSETTE, B. John Mar --. (1984). T JULY, R. (1964). ' African Hi KABA, L. (1974). T Africa. Evans' KACHAMA-NKOY, J. ( pensee de L. S.: Leopoldville (K KAGAME, A. (1943). Jn y' cimajyambere Pastorale. Bruss --. (1950). Bref ap· universitaires. --. (1952-53). Um --. (1956). La Philo des Sciences Col --. (1968). "La Place des religions africai --. (1970). Introducti Editions universitai --. (1971). "L'Ethno 1P raine, R. Klibansky, e --. (1972). Un abrege sitaires du Rwanda. --. (1976). La Philosophi KALANDA, M.A. (1967). La R' Brussels: Remarques A KALILOMBE, P.A. (1977). "Self~ tive." In African Theola New York: Orbis. er:0f,Production: Social Inequalities in Equatorial roduction in Africa, D. Grummey and C. C. t, s.l.: McGill University Center for De- 985). Mode of Production: The Chai. · ican Studies 19 ( 1) special issue. !:African Historiographies. Beverly 218 Bibliography ¥.ALU, o. u. (1977). "Church Presence in Africa: A Historical Analysis of the Evangelization Process." In African Theology En Route, Appiah-Kubi, K., and S. 1orres, eds. New York: Orbis. KANE, e, H. (:n:961). L'llventure ambigue. Paris: Julliard. KANE, M. (1982). Roman Africain et Tradition. Dakar: l\[ouvelles editions africaines. KANGAFU, K. (1973). Discours sur l'authenticite. Kinshasa: Presses Africaines. ¥-ANZA, T. (1959a). Le Congo a !a veille de son independance. Bruxelles: Les Amis de Presence Africaine. ----. (1959b). Propos d'un Congolais naif. Bruxelles: Les Amis de Presence Afocaine. KAOZE, s. (1907-19II). La Psychologie des Bantus et quelques lettres. Anastatic reproduction by A. J. Smet (1979). Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. KASHAMURA, A. (1973). Famille, sexualiti et culture. Paris: Payot. KAUMBA, L (1986). Dimensions de l'identite. Approche phenomenologique de !'univers romanesque de Mudimbe. Louvain-La-Neuve: Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation. KAUNDA, K. D. (1966). A Humanist in Africa: Letters to Colin NI. Morris. London: Longmans. KELLJER, A. s.; LISSITZYN, o.; and MANN, J. F. (1938). Creation of Rights of Sovereignty Through Symbolic Acts 1400-1800. New York: Columbia University Press. KENYATTA, J. (1938). Facing Mount Kenya. London: Secker and Warburg, New edition, 1962. New York: Vintage. KESTELOOT, L (1965). Les Ecrivains noirs de iangue fram;aise: Naissance d'une litteratttre. Brussels: lnstitm de Sociologie. ---. (1968). Negritude et situation colonial£. Yaounde: Cle. KILLINGRAY, D. (1973). A Plague of Europeans. Harrnondsworth: Penguin Education. KXMONF, L ( 197 5 ). Destin de ia litterature negro-africaine ou Problematique d'une culture. Kinshasa: Presses universitaires du Zaire. KINANGA, M. (1981). "L'Archeo!ogie foucauldienne. Une methode d'analyse du discours." In Langage et philosophie. Kinshasa: Facu!te de Theologie Catholique. KINGSLEY~ NL H. (1965). Travels in Wiest Africa. (Abridged version of 1900 edition). London: Cass. KINYONGO, J. (1970). Origine et signification du nom divin Yahve. Bonn: Bonner Biblische Beitrage. ---. (1973). L'Etre manifeste. Meditation philosophique sur /'affirmation de soi, la participation et l'authenticite au Zaire. Lubumbashi: Synthese. ---. (1979). ".Essai sur la fondation epistemologique d'une philosophie he1~ meneutique en Afrique: Le Cas de la discursivite." Presence Africaine no, 109:12-26. ---. (1982). "La Philosophie africaine et sor; histoire." Les Etudes philosophiques 4:407-18. KI-ZERBO, J. (1972). Histoire de l'Afrique d'hier a demain. Paris: Hatier. ---. (1980). "De l'Afrique ustensil.e a l'Afrique parternaire." In Africa's Dependence and the Remedies, V. Y. Mudimbe, ed. Paris: Berger-Levrault. KOFFI, N. (1976). "L'Impense de Towa et de Hountondji." Paper presented at the International Seminar on African Philosophy, Addis-Ababa, Dec. 1976. ---. (1977). "Les Modes d'existence materielle de la philosophie et la question de la philosophie africaine." Kore, Revue ivoirienne de philosophie et de Culture nos. 5, 6, 7, 2nd 8. KOFFI, N., and ABJDOU, T. (1980) "Controverses sur l'existence d'une philosophie africaine." 1n African Philosophy, C. Sumner, ed. Addis-Ababa: Chamber Printing House. Bibliography 219 KOM, A., ed. (1983). Dictionnaire des oeuvres litteraires negro-africaines de langue fran<;aised es origines a 1978. Sherbrooke: Editions Naaman. KOYRE, A. (1968tMetaphysics and Measurement. London: Chapman & Hall. KRADER, L. (1973), "Tile. Works of Marx and Engels in Ethnology Compared." lnternatiqnttfflf~fr,(~.tf!?f Social, History r~ (2). KUNST, H. J. (r967).d":Africam dans l art europeen. Cologne: Dumont Presse. LADRIERE, J. (r9 .,<,•. to Metaphore et Metonymie dans les Symboles Paremio}d ombe. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. LALEYE, I. (19 · •..d e la personne dans la pensee traditionnelle yoruba. --.(1975);1 question· --. (1981) Kinshasa --.(r982). tendu ou r23: 42'.""'. LANGER, W. L. (I, LAROUI, A. (r96 LATOUCHE, S., ( Les Temps LAUDE, J. (r979).,, LAURENTIN, R. (1 r26. LEACH, E. R. (r96 --. (1980). "Q, University o LECLERC, G. (r97z) LEGUN, C. (r958). LEIRIS, M. (r934). LEUSSE, H. DE. (r9 romanciers LEUZINGER, E. (196 LEVINE, V. T. (1986} Africa and t wood Press. LEVI-STRAUSS, C. (r95 Square Press, 19 --. (1958). Anthr New York: Basi --. (1962). La Pe,r sity of Chicago --. (r964). Le Cru Cooked. New Yo --. (r966). Du Miel Ashes. London: J. --. (r968). L'Origin (The Origin of Tab ~. ---. (197r). L'Homme 1J Row, r98r.) . · --. (r973). Anthropolo LEVY-BRUHL, L. (r949). Les sitaires de France. --. (r963). L'Ame prim uoi en Afrique? Une phenomenologie de la .:ifricaines." Langage et philosophie. que. philosophes africains. Triple malen, feconde." Presence Africaine no. 1890-1902. New York. ;l,la,risM: aspero. qppement du capitalisme." 220 Bibliography UENI-IARJDTG, . (1961) .. Divinity and Experience: The Religio•i of the Din/ea. Oxford: Oxford University f'ress. ussoTJBA, P. (r~ns). Conscience du deveioppement et democratie. Dakar-Abidjan: Nouvelles editions airicaines. LOFCHrn, M. E (1968). "Political Theory 2.nd African IPolitics," /ournd of Modem .African Studies 6. LOYJWI, L. (1979). Difference entre la generalite II du materialisnie dialectique et la generaliti II du rnat,iriafisme historique. Contribution a la critique de l'epistemologie althusslrienne. Doctoral dissert.1tion, Lubumbashi: ::aculte des Lettres. LONDON, L D. (1977). "Convergent and Divergent Amplification and its Meaning for Social Science!' Psychological P. .e ports no .• n: IIr-23. LUFULUABO, "· M. (1962). Vers une theodicee bantoue. Paris-Toumai. ---. (1964a) Orientation prechretienne de la conception bantoue de i'ztre, Leopoldville (Kinshasa): Centre cl'Etudes Pastorales. ---. (19646). La Notion luba-bantoue de l'etre, Tournai: Casterman. ---. (1966). Perspective theoiogique bantoue et theoiogie scholastique. JVlalines. LUGARD, F. (1905). A Tropical Dependancy. London: J. Nisbet. ---. (1965). The Dual Mandate in British Tropical Africa. Landon: Cass. LUMUMBA, P. (1963). Le Congo, terre d'avenir, est-il menace? Brussels: Office de Publicite. LY, A. (1956) Les Masses africaines et l'acuieile condition huraaine. Paris: Presence Africaine. LYNCH, H. R. (1967). Edward Wilmot Blyden: Pan-Negro Patriot 1832.-1912. London: Oxford University Press. ---, ed., (1978). Selected Letters of .Edward ',Viimot Blyden. New York: KIO Press. LYONS, R.H. (1975). To Wash an Aethiop White. Recherche, pedagogie et culture 56, IX, 68-73. ---. (1982b). L'Odeur du pere. Essai sur des iimites de la science et de la vie en Afrique noire. Paris: Presence Africaine. ----. (1982c) "fo Memoriam: Alexis Kagame (1911.-1981)." Recherche, pedagogie et culture, 56. ·· ---. (1983a). "An African Criticism of Christianity." Geneva-Africa 21 (2). ---. (19836). "African Philosophy as an Ideological Practice: The Case of French- Speaking Africa." African Studies Review 2.6, 3-4. MUDIMBE-BOYI, M. (1977). Testi e Immagini. La Missione de! "Congo" nelle Rela. zioni dei Missionari Cappucini Italiani 1645-1700. Dissertation. Lubumbashi. MUJYNYA, E. N. c. (1972). L'Homme dans l'univers des Bantu. Lubumbashi: Presses universitaires du Zaire. MU LAGO, v. (19 5 5). L'Union vitale bantu chez ies Bashi, les Banyarwanda, et !as Barundi face a !'unite vitale ecclesiale. Dissert8.tion. Rome: Propaganda. ---. (1959). "La Theologie et ses responsabi!ites." Presence Africaine no. 27-2.8. , _____ (196 5). Un visage africain du christianisme. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1973). La Religion traditionne!le des Bantu et leur vision du monde. Kinshasa: Presses universitaires du Zaire. ---. (1981). "Evangelisation et .Authenticite." Aspects du catholidsme au Zaire. Kinshasa: Facu!te de Theologie Catholique. MURDOCK, c. P. (19 59). Africa: Its Peoples and Their Culture History. New York: McGraw Hi!L MUZOREWA, G. H. (1985). The Origins and Development of African Theology. New York: Orbis. MUZUNGU, B. (1974). Le Dieu de nos peres. Bujumbura: Presses Lavigerie. MVJENG, E. (1965). L'A.rt d'Afrique noire. Liturgie et Langage religieux. Paris: Mame. ---. (1972.). Les Sources grecques de l'histoire negro-africaine. Paris: Presence Africaine. ----. (1978). "De la sous-mission a la succession." Civilisation noire et eglise catholique. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. ( r 9 8 3 ). "Recents developpements de la theologie africaine." Bulletin of African Theology 5, 9. N'DAW, A. (1966). "Peut-on parler d'une pensee africaine?" Presence Africaine no. 58:32-46. ----. (1983). La Pensee africaine. Recherches sur les fondements de la pensee negro·-africaine. Dakar: Nouvel!es editions africaines. Bibliography 223 NDUKA, o. (1974). "Africar: Traditional Systems of Thought aVJ.dT heir Implications for Nigeria's Education." Second Order 3 (r). NGIMBI-NSEKA. ( I 979 ). "Theologie et anthropologie transcendentale." Revue africaine de theologie 3, 5. NGINDU, A. (1968). "La Quatrieme Semaine Theologique de Kinshasa et la problematique d'une theologie africaine." La Revue du Clerge Africain 2, 4. ---. (1978). Le Problerne de la connaissance religieuse d'apres Lucien Laberthonniere. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. ---. (1979). "La Theologie africaine. De la polemique a l'irenisme critique,'' Bulletin of African Theology, I, (1), ---, ed. (1985)c The Mission of the Church Today. Kinshasa: Saint JPauL NGO!vIA, E. (1975). "Pour um: orientation authentique de la philosophie en Afrique: l'hermeneutique." Zaire-Afrique no. n3. ---. (1978). "La Recusation de la philosophie par la societe africaine." Melanges de phiiosophie africaine 3, 8 5-100. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. NGOUABI, M. (1975). Vers la construction d'une societe socialiste en Afrique. Paris: Presence Africaine. NGUVULU, A. (1971). L'Humanisme negro-africain face au developpement. Kinshasa: Okapi. NJOH-MOUELLE, N. (1970a). De la mediocrite a !'excellence. Yaounde: Cle. ---. (1970b). Ja/ons. Recherches d'une mentalite neuve. Yaounde: Cle. ---. (1975). Ja/ons II. L'Africanisme aujourd'hui, Yaounde: Cle. NKOMBE, o. (1977). "Methode er point de depart en philosophie africaine: authenticite et liberation." La Philosophie africaine 69-87, Kinshasa: facu!te de Theologie Catholique. ----. (1978a). "Essai de semiotique formelle: les rapports differentiels." Melanges de philosophie africaine 3: 131-48. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theoiogie Catholique. ---. (1978b). "Sagesse africaine et liberation," Philosophie et Liberation. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. ---. (1979) Metaphore et metonymie dans les symboles paremiologiques. L'Interrsubjectivite dans les proverbes tetelc., Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. NKOMBE, o., and SMET, A. J. (1978). "Panorama de la philosophie africaine comtemporaine," Melanges de philosophie africaine 3: 26 3-8 2. Kinshasa: Facuite de Theologie Catholique. NKRUMAH, K. (1957). Ghana. The Autobiography of Kwame Nkrumah, London: Thomas l\Telson, ---, (1961). I Speak of Freedom. London: Heinemann. ----. (1962). Towards Colonial Freedom. London: Heinemann, ---. (1963). Africa Must Unite. London: Heinemann. ----. (1965). N.eo-Colonialism: The Last Stage of Imperialism. London: Heinem;;;nn. ---. (1970), Consciencism. London: Panaf Books. NORDMANN-SEILER, A. (1976). La Litterature neo-africaine. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. NOTHOMB, D. (1965). Un humanisme africain. Brussels: Lumen Vitae. NSOKI, K, (1973). Problematique de la theologie af;,icaine. Dix ans de debats I960- I970. Unpublished thesis. Louvain University. NTENDIKA, J, (1966). L'Evolution de la doctrine du purgatoire chez St. Augustin. Paris: Etudes augustiniennes. ---. (1971). L'Evocation de l'au-dela dans la priere des marts. Etude de patristique et de iiturgie latines. Louvain-Paris: Beatrice Nauwelaerts, 224 Bibliography (1577). "Les .R.esponsabilite du departement de philosophie et religions :Jiricaines de k l'aculte de Theologie." La Philosophie africaine no. 1:9-J.o, Kinshasa: Faculte de Thfologie Catholique. ----. (1977-79). "La Theologie africaine. Bibhographie selective." Revue africaine de thiologie 2.~ 3~ 4, and 60 NT!EZIMANA, E.; I-IABERL/,ND, E; and others (1984). "Dossier: Alexis Kagame." Dialogue (Kigali), no. 102:19-8:L NYA!VHTI, c. (1978). "New Theological Approach and ·New Vision of the Church in Africa." Revue africaine de theologie 2, (3). NYEME, T. (1975). },ifunga. Ethique en milieu africain. Gentilisrne et christianisme. lngef"bohi: Imprirnerie du P. Theodose. NY:EREREJ,, (1967). Freedom and Unity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ---. (:r968a). Ujamaa. Essays on Socialism. London: Oxford Universit"y Press. ----. (1968b)o Freedom and Socialism. Oxford: Oxford University .Press, ---, (1973). Freedom and Development. Oxford: Oxford University Press, NZEGE, A, (:r980). Intelligence et guerre, Essai sur la philosophie politique de H. Bergson. Doctoral dissertation, Lubumbashi: faculte des Lettres. N'ZEMBELE, L (1983). "L'Avenir d'une derision: l.'ordre du discours africaino" Peuples noirs!peuples africains, no. 3 1, OBBO, c. (1980)0 African Women: Their Struggle for Economic Independence, London: Zed Press. OBENGA, T, (1973). L'Afrique dans l'antiquite. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1980), Pour une nouvelle histoire, Paris: Presence Africaine. ODER.A, H. o. (1972). "Mythologies as African Philosophy." East African Journal 9, IO. ---, ed, (1983). Philosophy and Cultures. Nairobi: Bookwise Limited. ODUYOYE, M. A. (1986). Hearing and Knowing. Theological Refiections on Christianity in Africa. New· York: Orbis. OFORI, P. E. (1977). Black African Traditional Religions and Philosophy: A Select Survey of the Sources from the Earliest Times to I974. Nendeln: Kto Press, OGILBY; J, (1670). Africa: being an accurate description of the regions of .A.egypt, Barbary, Lybia, and Billedulgerid, the land of the Negroes, Guinee, Aethiopia and the Abyssines. London: Thomas Johnson. OGOT, B. A. (1967). History of the Southern Luo. Nairobi: East African Publishing Houseo OKJERE, T. (1971). Can There Be an African Philosophy? A Hermeneutical Investigation with Special Reference to Ibgo Culture. Thesis. Louvain University, ---. (1978). "The Assumptions of African Values as Christian Values." Civilisation noire et eg!ise cathoiique. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---, (1983). African Philosophy. \Washington, D.C.: Universit'/ Press of .America. OKOLO, o. ( 1979 ). Tradition et destin. Essai sur la philosophie hermineutique de P, RicoeuJ·, lv1. Heidegger et I-I, G. Gadamer. Doctoral dissertation. Lumbumbashi: Faculte des Lettres. ---. (1980). "Tradition et destin: horizons d'une hennenemique phiiosophique africaine." Presence Africaine no. 114, OKONJI, M. o. (1975). "The Decolonization of the Social Sciences in Africa and Traditional .African Psychology." Thought and Practice 2 (2). o'LAUGHLIN, B. (1975). "Marxist Approaches in Anthropol.ogy." Annual Review of Anthropology 4:341--70. OLIVER, R. (1956). How Christian is Africa? London: Highway Press, 0LUMIDE, L J. (1948). The Religion of the Yorubas. Lagos. OMBREDANJE, A, (1969). L'Exploration de la mentalite des noirs. Paris: Presses universitaires de France. Bibliography 225 o'MEARA, P., and G. M. CARTER, eds. (1986). African Independence: The First Twenty-Five Years. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. OMOYAJOWO, A. (1984). Diversity and Unity: The Development and Expansion of the Cherubim and Seraphim Church in Nigeria. New York: University Press of America. ONYANWU, K. c. (1975). ''African Religion as an Experienced Reality." Thought and Practice 2 (2). ONYEWUENI, I. c. (1982). "A Philosophical Reappraisal of African Belief in Reincarnation." Presence Africaine no. 123. ORTEGA Y GASSET, J., (1973). An Interpretation of Universal History. New York: Norton. ORTIGUES, M. c., and ORTIGUES, E. (1973). Oedipe Africain. Paris: u. G. E. owusu, M. (1970). Uses and Abuses of Political Power, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ---. (1978). "The Ethnography of Africa: The Usefulness of the Useless." American Anthropologist 80 (2):310-34. PADMORE, G. (1971). Pan-Africanism or Communism. New York: Doubleday. PARRINDER, G. (1954). African Traditional Religion. London: Hutchinson's University Library. --. (1958). Witchcraft. London: Penguin. P'BITEK, o. (1970). African Religions in Western Scholarship. Nairobi: East African Literature Bureau. ---. (1971). Religion in Central Luo. Nairobi. ---. (1973). Africa's Cultural Revolution. Nairobi: Macmillan. PERSON, Y. (1968-1975). Samori. 3 vol. Dakar: lnstitut Fondamental d'Afrique Noire. PIROTTE, J. (1973). Periodiques missionaires belges d'expression fran<;aiseR. eflets de cinquante annees d'evolution d'une mentalite. Louvain: Publications Universitaires. PUNY. (1942). Natural History. An English translation by H. Rackham, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. POMONTI, J. c. (1979). L'Afrique trahie. Paris: Hachette. POPPER, K. (1949). The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. PORTERES, R. (19 50). "Vieilles agricultures de l'Afrique intertropicale." Agronomie tropicale 5:489-507. ---. (1962). "Berceaux agricoles primaires sur le continent africain." Journal of African History 3:195-210. POUILLON, F., (1976). L'Anthropologie economique: courants et problemes. Paris: Maspero. POWELL, E. (1984). Private Secretary (Female)/Gold Coast. New York: St. Martin's Press. PRATT, v. (1972). "Science and Traditional African Religion." Second Order 1:(1). Pretres noirs s'interrogent (Des) (19 57). Paris: Cerf. RABEMANANJARA, J. (s.d.). "Alioune Diop, le cenobite de la culture noire." Hommage a Alioune Diop fondateur de Presence Africaine. Rome: Editions des Amis de Presence Africaine. RADIN, P. (1927). Primitive Man as Philosopher. New York-London: Appleton. RALIBERA, R. (1959). "Theologien-Pretre africain et le developpement de la culture africaine." Presence Africaine nos. 27-28. RANDALL-MACIVER, D. (1906). Medieval Rhodesia. London: Macmillan. RANGER, T. (1967). Revolt in Southern Rhodesia 1896-97: A Study tn African Resistance. London: Heineman. --. (1969). The African Churches of Tanzania. Nairobi: East African Publishing House. 226 Bibliography ---. (1985). "Religious Movements and Politics in Sub-Saharan Africa." Review essay for the SSRC/ACLS Joint Committee on African Studies, ASA annual meeting, New Orleans. RANGER, T. and KIMAMBO, 1., eds. (1972). The Historical Study of African Religion. London: Heinemann. REED, c. A., ed. (1977). Origins of Agriculture. The Hague: Mouton. RENCONTRES INTERNATIONALES DE BOUAKE. (1965). Tradition et modernisme en Afrique noire. Paris: Seuil. ---. (1965). Les Religions africaines traditionnelles. Paris: Seuil. REY, P. P. (1966). "The Lineage Mode of Production." Critique of Anthropology, 3:27-79. ---. (1971). Colonialisme, neo-colonialisme et transition au capitalisme. Exemple de la "comilog" au Congo-Brazzaville, Paris: Maspero. ---. (1973). Les Alliances de classes. Paris: Maspero. RICOEUR, P. (1955). Histoire et verite. Paris: Seuil. (History and Truth. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1965.) ---. (1969). Le Conflit des interpretations: Essais d'hermeneutique. Paris: Seuil (The Conflict of Interpretations. Evanston: Northwestern University Press). ---. (1984). The Reality of the Historical Past. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. RIESMAN, P. ( 19 8 5 ). "The Person and the Life Cycle: African Social Life and Thought." Review essay for the SSRC/ACLS Joint Committee on African Studies, ASA annual meeting, New Orleans. RI,l"iBY, P. (1969). Cattle and Kinship among the Goga. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ---. ( 19 8 5 ). Persistant Pastoralists: Nomadic Societies in Transition. London: Zed. ROBINSON, R.; GALLAGHER, J.; and DENNY, A. (1961). Africa and the Victorians: The Climax of Imperialism in the Dark Continent. New York: St. Martin's Press. RODEGEM, F. M. (1961). Sagesse kirundi. Tervuren: Musee Royal de l'Afrique Centrale. ---. (1973). Anthologie rundi. Paris: A. Colin. RODNEY, w. (1981). How Europe Underdeveloped Africa. Washington, D.C.: Howard University Press. ROMANO, G. F. (1648). Breve Relatione del successo della Missione de Frati Minari Cappuccini del Serafico P. S. Francesco al Regno del Congo. Roma: Sacra Congregatione de Propaganda Fide. ROMBAUT, M. (1976).La Parole noire. Paris: Editions Saint-Germain-des-Pres. ---. (1976). Nouvelle poesie negro-africaine. Paris: Editions Saint-Germain-desfus. , ROTBERG, R. I. (1970). Africa and its Explorers: Motives, Method anJ Impact. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. RUCH, E. A. (1974). "ls There an African Philosophy?" Second Order 3 (2). SACHS, 1. (1971). La Decouverte du tiers monde. Paris: Flammarion. SAGAN, c. (1983). Broca's Brain: Reflections on the Romance of Science. New York: Ballantine Books. SAHLINS, M. (1976). Culture and Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. SAID, E. (1978). Orientalism. New York: Pantheon. SANDERS, E, R. (1969). "The Hamitic Hypothesis: Its Origin and Functions in Time Perspective." Journal of African History IO (4). SANNEH, L. (1983). West African Christianity: The Religious Impact. New York: Orbis. SARRAUT, A. (1923). La Mise en valeur des colonies fran,;aises. Paris: Payot. l Bibliography SMffRE, J. P. (1943). L'Etre et le N.eant. Paris: Gallimard. (Being and Nothingness. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1956.) ----. (1953). Qu'est-ce que la titterature? Paris: Gall.irn:::,rd. ---. (1956). Situations V. Paris: Gallimard. ---. (1960). Critique de la raison dialectique. Paris: Gallimard. ---. (1976). Bi'ack Orpheus. Paris: Presence Africaine. SAUL, J. (1977). Natio11alism, Socialism and Tanzanian history. In African Sociai Studies, P. C. YJVG. utkind and P. Waterman, eds. New York: Monthly Keview Press. SCHMESTA, P. (1963). Le Sens religieux des primitifs. Paris: I\/Iame. SCHEUB, H. (1971). (1972). Bibliography o/ African Ora! Narratives. lVladison: University of Wisconsin Press. ---. (1977). African Oral Narratives, Proverbs, Riddles, Poetry and Song. Boston: HalL -----. (198 5). "A Revie•.v of African Ora! Traditions and Literature." African Studies Review 26 (2--3):1-72. SCHILLING, R., ed. (1944). La Veillee de Venus. Peruigilium Veneris. Paris: Collection Bude. SCHIPPER DELEEUW, M. (1973). Le Blanc vu d'A.frique. Yaounde: Cle. SCHMmT, w, (1931). The Origin and Growth of Religion. London: Methuen. ---. (1933-49). Die Ursprung der Gottesidee. Munster: Aschendorff. SCHOLTE, B. (1983). "Cultural Anthropology and the Paradigm Concept: A Brief Histor; of their Recent Convergence." In Functions and Uses of Disciplinary Histories, L. Graham, '7/. Lepenies, and E Weingart, eds. Dordrecht, Boston: D. Reidel. SCHUMPJE17ER, J. A. (1951). Imperialism and Social Classes. Nev, York: A. M. Kelley. SCHWARZ, A. (1979). Colonialistes, africanistes et africains. Louiseville-Jvlontreal: Nouvelle Optique. ---, ed. (1980). Les Faux Pro;uhetes de !'Afrique ou !'afi·(eu)canisme. Quebec: Presses de l'Uni1;ersite Laval. SJEBAG, L (1964). 11/larxisme et structuralisrne. Paris: Payot. SEIDMAN, A. (198 5). The Roots of Crisis in Southern Africa. Trenton: Africa ~world JPresso SENE, A. (1966). Sur le chemin de li:i negritude. Cairo: Imprimerie Catholique de Beyrouth. SENGHOR, L s. (1961). Natior, et voie africaine du socialisrae. Paris: fresence Africaine. ---. (1962). Pierre Teilhard de Chardin et la politique africaine. Paris: SeuiL ---. (1964). Liberte I: Flegritude et humanisme. Paris: Seuil. ---, (1967a). Negritude, arabisme, et f-rancite. Beirut: Dar Al-Kitab AIJubnani. ---. (1967b). Les Fondeme:-its de l'africanite ou Negritude et arabiti. ?aris: Presence Africaine. ----, (1971). Liberti !I: nation et voie africaine du soda!israe. Paris: SeuiL ---, (1972.). "Pourquoi une ideologie negro-africaine?" Presence A/ricaine no. 82:n-38. ---, (1976a). Pour 1me relect:ure africa,:ne de Mm-x et d'Engels. Dakar-Abidjan: :Nouvelles Editions africaine:,. ---. (1976b). "Authenticite et w~gritnde:" Zaire-.Afrique, no. ro2:8I-86. ---. ( r 977). Libert.§ III: 1tegri1udee t civilisation .de l'u11iue?se!P. aris: SeuiL ----. ( r 9 8 3 ). Liberti JV: soci,1/isme el plcmirication. Paris: Seuil. SETILOA"'IE, G. (1976). Image o( God Among the Sotho-Tswana. Rotterdam: Balkema. SETILOANE, G. M. (1977). "Where Are We in Africa-n.,l'beoiogy?" In A(ria.n Theology En Route, A.ppiah-Kubi and Torr,es eds. l'-Tev,Y, ol'k: Orbis. Bibliography SHNW, T. M:. (1935). Towards A Politirn! Econoniy fc,r lifrica: The Dialectics of Dependence. Nevv York: St .. M.artin's Pr,::ss. SHELTON~~•., J. (1963). "Le PriE:::ipe cyclique de ia personnaiit§ africaine." Presence A.7nc(J'lne r.,os. 45--46. •-----. (1968). "Causality in African Thought: Igbo and Other." Practical An·· thropology, r 5. SHEPPERSON, G. (1960). "Notes on l'\Jegro-A,merican Influences on the Emergence of African Nationalism." Journal of African History, r, 2, SHIVJI, L (1976). Class Struggles in Tam;ania. Londcn: Heinemann. SHORTER, A. (1977). Africa:t Christian Theology. t,Iew York: Orbis. SMJ::T, A. J. (19751). "Bibliographie selective des £eligions traditiorrnelles cie !'.Afrique noire" Cahiers des reiigions africaine:;, 17-13. ---. ( 197 5 b ). Philosophie africaine. Textes choisis et bibhographie selective, 2 vol. Kinshci_sa: Presses nniversitaires du Zaire. ---. (1977a). "Histoirrc de la philosophie africaine, pro6lemes e1: raechodes," La Philosophie Africaine, 47---68. Kinshasa: faculte de Thfologie C::Mholiquie, ----. (19776). "Le Pere Placide 1empds et son oeuvre publiee." Revue africaine de theologie r, I. ---. (1977c). "La Jamaa d2.ns l'oeuvre du Pere Placide Tempels." Cahiers des :religions africaines, r 1, 21-22, r. -----. (1977d). "Histoire de la philosophie airicaine, pro6lemes et methodes." La Philosophie A.fricaine. Kinshasa: faculte de Theologie Catholique. ---. (1978a). "Le Concept fonclamenw! de l'ontologie bantu." Texte inedit du Pere Placide Tempds. Melanges de philosophie africaine 3, q.9-80. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theo:iogie Catholique. ---. (1978b). "Bibliographie selective c1e la philosophie africaine. Repertoire chronologique." 181-262. Melange:: de Philosophie Africaine, op. cit. ----. (1980). Histoire de la Philosophie Alricaine Conternporaine. Kinshasa: faculte de Theologie Catholique. SMHH, P. (19702_) "L2. Forge de !'intelligence." L'I-Io;nme ro, 2. --··-- (19706). "La Lance d'une jeune hlle," fo Echanges et communications, Melanges offerts a Cl. Levi-Strauss, ]. Pouillon ei: P. M.aranda, eds. Paris: La Haye. ----. (1975). Le Recit Popu!aire au Rwanda. Paris: Classiqu.es Africains. SIJOV✓DEN, F. M, (1,no), Blacks in Ar:tiqui:y: Ethiopians in the Greco-Roman Ext1erience. Cambridge: Harvarc\ University I''ress, SOIDIPO, J. o. (1973). "Notes on the concept oi Cause and Chance in Yoruba Traclitional Thoaght." Second Order 2 (2). ----. (1975). "Philosophy in Afric:: Todiy." Thought ard Practice J. (2). ---, (1983). "?hilosophy, Science, Technol,:igy and 'Ii::s.::Htiona!A frican Thought," In Philosophy and Cultures, H. n Ornka, ed. l'-Tairobi: Bookwise Ltd. SOUSBERGHE, L. DE. (1951). "Apropos de 'La Philosophie b::ntcue'." Zaire 5:8:cI- 28. SOUTHALL, A. (1976). "Orientations in Political .Anthropoiogy." C,anadian Journal of African Studies 10 (2), ---. (1983). "The Contributiofl_ o' Anthropology to Afocan Studies." African Studies Review 26, (3/4). SOUZA, G, DJE. ( 197 5 ). La Conception de "vie" chez les Fons. Cotonou: EditioDs du Benin. sow, I. E. B. (1977). Psychiatrie dynamique africaine. Paris: Payot. ---, (1978). Les Structures anthrnpologiques de la (oiie en Afrique ,wire. Paris: Payoc SOYINKA, w. (1976). Nlyth, Literatur.i and the African Vf/orld. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bibliography 229 STAVENHAGEN, R. (1971). "Decolonializing Applied Social Sciences." Human Organization 30 (4). SUMNER, c., ed. (1974-1981). Ethiopian Philosophy: I, 1974, The Book of the Wise Philosophers; II, 1974, The Treatise of Zi:ir'a Yacob and of Walda Haywat; III, 1978, The Treatise of Zi:ir'a Yacob and of Walda Haywat; IV, 1981, The Life and Maxims of Skandas. Addis-Ababa: Central Printing Press. --. (1980). African Philosophy. Philosophie Africaine. Addis-Ababa: Chamber Printing House. --. (1983). ''An Ethical Study of Ethiopian Philosophy." In Philosophy and Cultures, H. 0. Oruka, ed. Nairobi: Bookwise Ltd. SUNDKLER, B. (1964). Bantu Prophets in South Africa. London: Oxford University Press. ---. (1976). Zulu Zion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. SURET-CANALE, J. ( 19 5 8 ). Afrique noire occidentale et centrale. Paris: Editions Sociales. TAYLOR, J. v. (1963). The Primal Vision. London: SCM Press Ltd. TCHIDIMBO, E. M. (1963). L'Homme noir dans l'eglise. Paris: Presence Africaine. TEMPELS, P. (1945). La Philosophie bantoue. Elisabethville: Lovania. (Paris: Presence Africaine, 1949). ---. (1959). Bantu Philosophy. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1962). Notre rencontre I. Leopoldville (Kinshasa): Centre d'Etudes Pastorales. · ---. (1979). Philosophie bantu. Introduction and revision of the Rubbens translation by A. J. Smet. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. TERRAY, E. (1969). Le Marxisme devant Les societes primitives. Paris: Maspero. THEUWS, J. A. T. (1951). "Philosophie bantoue et philosophie occidentale." Civilisations, I. ---. (1954). "Textes luba." Bulletin trimestriel du Centre d'Etudes des Problemes Sociaux lndigenes 27:1-153. --. (1983). Word and World. Luba Thought and Literature. St. Augustin: Verlag des Anthropos-Instituts. THOMAS, L. v. ( 19 5 8). "Posivitisme et metaphysique. Reflexions apropos de la culture noire." Aspects de la culture noire. Paris: Fayard. ---. (1960). "Un systeme philosophique senegalais: la cosmologie Diola" Presence Africaine nos. 3 2-3 3. ---. (1982). La Mort africaine. ldeologie funeraire en Afrique noire. Paris: Payot. THOMAS, L. v.; LUNEAU, R.; and DONEUX, J. L. (1969). Les Religions d'Afrique noire. Paris: Fayard/Denoel. THORNTON, A. P. (1959). The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies. London: Macmillan. THORNTON, R. (1983). "Narrative Ethnography in Africa 1850--1920: The Creation and Capture of an Appropriate Domain for Anthropology." Man 18 (3). TOBNER, o. (1982). "Cheikh Anta Diop, l'heretique." Peuples noirs, peuples africains 30:85-91. TORT, P., and DESALMAND, P. (1979). Sciences Humaines et Philosophie en Afrique. La Difference Culturelle. Paris: Hatier. TOURE, s. (19 59a). Experience guineenne et unite africaine. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1959b). Guinee. Prelude a l'independance. Paris: Presence Africaine. ---. (1959c). Republique de Guinee. Conakry: Imprimerie Patrice Lumumba. TOWA, M. (197m). Leopold Sedar Senghor: negritude OU servitude. Yaounde: Cle. ---. (1971b). Essai sur la problematique philosophique dans l'Afrique actuelle. Yaounde: Cle. --. (1979). L'ldee d'une philosophie africaine. Yaounde: Cle. TRILLES, R. P. (1931). Les Pygmies de la foret equatoriale. Paris: Bloud et Gay. Bibliography TSHIAMALiENGA, N. (1973). "La Vision ntu de l'homme. Essai de philosophie linguistique et anthropologique." Cahiers des religions africaines 7:176-99. -----. (197 4). "La Philosophie de la faute clans la tradition luba." Cahiers des religions africaines 8:167-86. ----. (:r977a). "Qu'est-ce que la 'philosophie africaine." La Philosophie Africaine I, 3 3-46. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. ---. (1977b). "Langues bantu et philosophie. Le cas du ciluba." La Philosophie africaine I:147-58. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Cathoiique. ---. (1980). Denlwn und Sprechen Ein Beitrag zum Relativitats Prinzip am Beispiel einer Bantusprache (Ciluba). Dissertation. Frankfurt/.Main. ---. (1981). "La Philosophie dans la situation actuelle de l'Afrique." Combats pour un Christianisme africain. Kinshasa: faculte de Theologie Catholique. TSHIBANGU, T. (I96 5 ). Theologie positive et theologie speculative, Position traditionnelle et nouvelle problematique. Louvain-Paris: Beatrice Nauvve!aerts. ---. (1974). Le Propos d'une theologie africaine. Kinshasa: Presses universitaires du Zaire. ---. (1977). ''L'Afrique noire et le christianisme." Cahiers des religions africaines I I, 21-22, I. ---. (1980). Theologie comme science au XXe siecle. Kinshasa: Presses universitaires du Zaire. TSHIBANGU, T. and VANNESTJE, A. (1960). "Debat sur la theologie africaine." Revue du Clerge Africain r 5. TSHIBANGU, w. M. (1972). Science et superstition chez A. Comte. Ph.D. dissertation. Dijon: Faculte des Lettres. TURGOT, A. R. J. (1913-1923). Oeuvres de Turgot et documents le concernant, avec une bibliographie et notes, G. Schelle, ed. Paris, 5 vols. TURNBULL, c M. (1962). The Lonely African. Ne-cwY ork: Simon and Schuster. TURNER, v. w. (1952), The Lozi Peoples of North-Wlestern Rhodesia. London: International African Institute. ---. (1964-) Schism and Continuity in an African Society. Manchester: Manchester University Press. ----. (1969). The Ritual Process. Chicago: Aldine. ---·. (1975). Revelation and Divination in Ndembu Ritual. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ----, (198 r). The Drums of Affliction: A Study of Religious Processes among the Ndembu of Zambia. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. TUTU, D. (1984). Hope ancl Suffering. Grand Rapids: W. B. Eerdmans. UGIRASHEBUJA, o. (1977), Dialogue entre la poesie et la pensee dans !'oeuvre de 1--Ieidegger. Brussels: Lumen Vitae. VAN CAENEGHAM, R. (1956). La Notion de Dieu chez les Balubas du Kasai,. Brussels: Academie Royde des Sciences Coloniales. VAN LIERDE, J, (1963). La Pensee politique de Patrice Lumuraba. Paris: Presence Africaine. VAN DBiERBERGH, c. (1913), Les Negres de l'Afrique. Bmxelles: A. de Wit. VAN PARYS, J. M:, (1978). "Philosophie en Afrique. Analyse du seminaire sur la phiiosophie africaine d'Addis-Abeba. 1-3 December 1976." Melanges de philosophie africaine. Kinshasa: faculte de Theologie CathoHque. ---. (c98:r). "Etat actuel de l'activite philosophique en Afrique." Langage et societe. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie CathoHque. VANSINA, J. (1961). De la tradition orale. Essai de methode historique. Tervuren: Musee Royal de l'Afrique Centrale. ---. (1965), Les Anciens Royaumes de la savanne. Kinshasa: fostitut de Recherches Economiques et Sociales. Bibliography ---. (19722.). La Legende du passe: traditions oraies du Burundi. BrusselsTervuren: M.usee }Loyal de i'Afrique Centrale. ---, (1972b). "Once Upon a Time: Oral Traditions as History in Africa." In Historical Studies Today, E Gilbert and S. R. Graubard, eds. ---. (1978). The Children of Woot: A History of the Kuba Peoples. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, ---. (1983). "Is Elegance a Proof? Structuralism and African History." History in Africa ro:307-48. VAN WKNG, J, (1949), "Hmnanisme chretien africain." Lumen Vitae 4 (1). VAUGHAN, A. T. (1982). "From 'Y/hite 11/ian to Redskin: Changing Anglo-Arneriean Perception of the American Indian," The American History Review 87. VERGER, P. (1968). Flux et reflux de la traite des negres entre le Golf du Benin et Bahia de Todos os Santos du XV 0 au XJXe siecie. Paris: Mouton. VERHAEGiENB,. (1974). Introduction a l'histoire immediate, Gembloux: Duculot. ---. (1978). L'Enseignement universitaire au Zaire. Paris: L'l-iarmattan, ---. (1979). "Religion et politique en Afrique noire." Religions africaines et christianisme 1, 179-94. Kinshasa: Faculte de Theologie Catholique. VETO, M. (1962). "Unite et dualite de la conception du mal chez les Bantu orientaux," Cahiers d'Etudes Africaines 8. VEYNE, P. (1984). Wlriting History. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press. VILAsco, G. (1983), "Philosophie, anthropologie et culture." In Philosophy and Cultures, H. Go Oruka ed. Nairobi: Bookwise Ltd. VINCKE, J, L (1973). Le Prix du peche. Essai de psychanalyse existentiel!e des traditions europeenne et Africaine. Kinshasa-Lubumbashi: Mont Noir. WAGNER, J. (1962). Les Poetes noirs des Etats-Unis. Paris: IsmJ.. WAGNER, R. (1981). The Invention of Culture, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. WALLERSTEIN, L (1961\ Africa: The Politics of Independence. New York: Random House. ---. (1967), Africa: The Politics o/ Unity. New York: Random House. ---. (1979). The Capitalist World Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ---. (1983). "The Evolving Role of the Africa Scholar in African Studies." African Studies Review 26 (3-4):155-61. WAMBA-DIA-'WAMBA, E. (1980). "La Pbilosophie en Afrique ou Les defis de l'Africain philosophe." In Les Faux Prophetes de l'Afrique au l'Afr(eu)canisme, A. Schwarz, ed. Quebec: P.cesses de !'Universite Laval. WASSING, R. s. (1969). L'Art de l'Afrique noire. Fribourg: Office du Livre. WAUTHrnR, e, (1964). L'Afrique des Africains. foventaire de la negritude. Paris: Seuil. \VEBJER, M. (1978). Economy and Society. Berkeley: University of California Press. WHITE, H. (1979). "Michel Foucault." Structuralism and Since. ]. Sturrock, ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. WILLAME, J, c, (1971). "Recherches sur les modes de production cynegetique et lignager." L'Homme et la Societe 19:rnr-20. ---, (1976). "L'Autre Face du ro-1aume ou, Le 1V1euri:rdeu pere." Geneve-A/rique 15 (1). WILLIAMS, G, (1967). The Expansion of Europe in the XVIIIth Century. Overseas Rivalry. Discovery and Exploitation. Nevv York: Walker &:. Company. WILSON, B. R,, ed. (1970). Rationality. Oxford: Basil BlackwelL WIREDU, J.E. (1973). "Logic and Ontol.ogy" Second Ordei- 2 (1-1.). ---. (1977). "How Not to Compare African Thought with Western Thought." In African Philosophy: An Introduction, R. "Wright, ed, Washington: Universi.ty Press of America. Bibliography ---, (19So). Philosophy and African Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. WITTE, c. M, DE. (1958). "Les EuHes _pontificales et l'expansion portugaise au XVe siede." Revue d' his to ire ecc!esiastique 5 3. WOL?E, H., ed. (1980). The Articulation of Modes of Production. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. "il'/ORLD BANK. (1984). Toward Sustained DevelotJment in Sub-Saharan .Africa, Washington, D.C.: The World Bank. WRIGHT, R. (1977). African Philosophy: An Introduction. Washington: Universitl/ Press of America. YAI, o. (1977). "Theory and Practice ir; African Philosophy: The Poverty of Speculative Philosophy." Second Order 6 (2). French version: Presence Africaine (1978) no. 108. YOUNG, M. c. (1965). Politics in the Congo. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ---. (1982). Ideology and Development in Africa. New Haven: Yale University Press. ZAHAN, D, (1959). Societes d'initiation barnbara. Paris: Mouton. ---. (1963). La Dialectique du verbe chez les Bambara. Paris: Mouton. ---. (I979). The Religion, Spirituality, and Thought of Traditional Africa. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, zoA, L (1957). Pour un nationalisme chretien au Cameroun. Yaounde: Saint Paul. zuuRE, B. (1932). L'Ame du Niurundi. Paris: Beauchesne. INDEX. Abdou, T., 160 Abraham, W. E., 39-41, 7'3 Acndturati.on, 2.0, 68, 19I-92 Ac:aptation, theologies of, 5 7 Adotevi, S., 36-37, 167 Adventures in a Mitd Hut (Barley), 2.I-22 Afana, ()sende 1 96 Africa (Schulte~), u African A!/egory (Ripa), 12 Africa and the Africans (Blyden), 99, me African Empires and Civilizations (lviichdet), 88 A/rican Genesis (Frobenius), 182 African gene~is, hypotheses of, I 6, 22 African.ism, 91 166-68, 176'.I I79; Blyden's attitude toward, 124 P1.fricanity,3 71 79 African languages') 60~ I23, 169; missionaries' 2.nd anthropologists' knowledge of, 65-66 African nation, concept of, r::: 5-16 African Personality, 3 8; Blyden as precurcso:i'.' of, 98, 131. See also Black personality African Studies, 9, J6, 44, 169, r23 A(rique ambiguii (Balandier), 38 Aguolo, C., 161 .Ahidjo, .A., I 8 5-86 Ajayi, J. F. A., 194-9 5 Akarnbas (people), I 52 Alexander './I (pope), "i· 5 "Alogicality of lll'monality, The"' (Bodumin), 162 Alterity. See Otherness Althusscr, L., 158, 160, 179 Americz.n Colonizarion Society, 103, 104 }u11ia, S., 5 Amo, A, G., 16?. i\.nglican Church, 2e9, 5 5 Anobo, M,: OE Senghor, 94 Anthropoiogicd philosophy. See fahnophilosophy Anthology of New Negro and Malagasy Pcetry (Senghor), 83-84 Anthropology, 16-22, 37, 67-69, 75-78, r2, 1-85; Africa1, critique of, 38; and African sociology, 166; Blyden compared to founders oi, II9; and Christiani,y, 56-58; commitment to African values, 60, SS-89; concept of primitive philosophy, 135, 1.;.2; on distance fro111 San"!e to Other, 8 r; and ethnocentrism, I9'; Foucault on;) r6~ 29; in1- pact on black intelligentsia, 88; LeviStrauss on, 28-29; and ma~·ginality, 6; miss10_ rnne~ information as, 64-67; negritude's influenr;e, 8 5, 8 6; arrd philology, I8; and philosophy~ 152, 158, 168; on prim'tive philosophies, r4 3-,,4; relationship w history, 176, 178; struc,uralisc, I 9 8; Tempels' differentiation from, = 3 7 Anyidoho, K., I 82 Arabic language: Blyden on, 123, I26 Arendt, Hannah: on racism, 108 Aristotelianisn::., Lq6, 14 7 A.rnold, So, 182 .A..r t.i. African, 9- I 2 Art, European: depiccion of Africans, 6-9, u Arusha Declaration, 9 5 Astmnomy, 13-15 Authenticii:y, 153, 169, r74 Avenement de l'Afrique noire: .. , , L' (Bilinschwig), 38-39 kNolowo, 0,, 9 :i Azikiwe, Nnamdi, 90, 95, 93, 131 Azombo-Menda, S. M.: on Senghor, 94 Ba, A. Harnpate, 96 Bachelard, G., 137 Baeta, C. G., 5 5 Bahoken, J. C: on Christianity, 'jtt Baker, Sir Samuel, I I 8 Balance Sheets of Imperialism (Clark), 3 Balandier, Georges, 80, 88, 89~ :r66, 177; AJ'riqw? ambiguii, 3 8 "Eantou Probk-aatique, Le" (Eboussi- Boulaga), 157-58 Bantu (people), 50, 53-54, 138-39, 169 Bantu languages, 145-46 Bantu philosophy, 5!;; Crahay's lecture on, 154, 155-56; Kagame on, 145-52.; Te1npels on, 135-4.1., 144, rs,-52 Ban;u Philosophy (Tempels), :;o, 67, 136-42, 144, 149, 153, 178; Crahay on, 155; Kagame 011, 146 Banyarwanda (people), language of, ~,62 Barley, N., 21-22 Bi.rth,~s, R., 129 Basic Bthiopian Philo5c,t:,hicaTle xts (Sumner, ed,), 202 Baurnstark, i,., 16 3 Being, 28, 162.; in Bantu philosophy, 138-41, q.7-48; in Western philosophy, 140. See also Ontology lJei;-zga nd f-._~?thi11gne(Sssa rtre\ 8 5 Bell0nz.n, R L., 18 3 Benedict )?:_J(Ip ope), 5 3 Bib;e, 123, 128; ,& prnbiem Gi cultural differences, 8-9. See a/sc Gospel, the Bilinguality: of missionaries and anthropologists, 66-67 Bigo, E: OH marginalir-1, 5 Bimwenyi, 0., x, 39-40, 168 Bird, C. S.: Explorations in African Systems o/ Thought, I 99 Blz.ck Africans: portrayals of, in European paint.;_ngs, 7-9, 12 Black (Negro) Americans, 90, II7, 130; Blyden on, 98, Io4,_ 105-107, 111 1 130, 132; Nkrumah influenced by, 88 Black consciousness: Blyden on, JI:21 "Black Islam," r8s Blackness: Blyde•1's restric,:ive meaning, 104, 132 Black Orpheus (Sartre), 83-85, 90-91, 92, 132 Black personality, 87-88, 98, n8-24, 131, 132., 166; emphasis on, in Christianity, 58, 60; rhetoric of, 3 6; as stra,egy, 194 Black responsibility: Blyden OD, rn9 Bloch, M.: on history, 1 9 5 Blyden, E.W., 80-81, 98-134; Africa and the A/ricans, 99, ma; Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race, 99-129, 133; on B1ack Arnericans, 98~. IOLj., ro5-ro7~ III, I30~ 131.; on colonization, 99-rn7; criticisill of European tradition, I 11-q.; on education, 99-roo~ ::.::02-Io3; Liberia: Past) Present and Future, 99; Liberia's Of/ering, 99, 104, 106, 122; Negrn in Ancient History, 99, 100, 109; political theory, u4-r8, 124, 128-29, 132; Vindication o( the Negro Race, 99, rn8 Boas, F., 18 Bodunrin, E 0., 162 Boesak, A. A., 173 Book of the \Vise Philosophers (Stnmer, eel.), 163, 201, 203 Boulle, P.: Planet o( the Apes quoted, r, 5-6, 2.J}, 28, 35-36, 44, 64., 83,145,153 Bourgeois, A., 69 Brande:, E, 180, 188-89, 195 Bricolage, 3 1, 3 2 Brunschwig, H., 3 8-3 9 Buakasa, T. K., 174 Buffon, 72, 119 Bulletin o( African Theology, 179 Burgkmair, Hans: Exotic Tribe, 6--7, 8-9 Buthalezi: on indigenization, 63 Cai,iers des religions af,-icaines (Mulago), 171 Cannibalism: as pagan trait, 49-50 Capital;sm, 2-3, 165, 196-97 Capicein, Jacobus, 162 Carnzts de Lucien Levy-Bruh/, Les (LevyBruhl), r 5 4-5 5 Cavergne de Bongo, La (film), "I· Index Certeau, M., de, 5I Cesair,e, _A.im,~2~, 36, 83~ 141, I58; .Discourse on Colonialism, 90, 9~, 153 ChaiHet-Bert, J., 20 Ch2jn of being, 9, 13, 27 Christianis1ne sans fitiche: Revelation et Domination (Eboussi-Boulaga), 173 Christianity, 2oi I52') I70, I72-73; }drican response to, 51, 54-64; and anthropology, 56-58; attempts t'.J justify, 178-79; as background of African intellectuals, 39-4.0; Blyden en, II2, 16, 124-28, 130. See also P•otestant churches; Roman Catholicism; Theology Christianity, Is/a1,1 and the Negro Race (Blyden), 99-192, 133 Christopher, A. J., 4 7 Civilization: equated with Christianity, 20, 49, 31, 53 Clark, Grover, 3 Classics, study of, u 3 Classification, 6, 9, :, 3; in Bantu philosophy, 138-39, 14-6-47, q.9 Ciassiques Africains (Dampierre), 18I-82 Ciifford, J,, 66 Clirnate: as barrier to colonization, ! o 5,. I 07 Cogito, 147, 190 Coherence Theory, 67 Collective memory: myth as, 144 Collingwood, R. G., Sr Colonialism, !-5, 16, 76, 93, 170, 191; definition of~ 1; lVIarxist theory of, 3-4; 1nissionary role in, 44-4 7; negritudc as resist" nce to, 83, 88; Sartre on, 85; Temp!es' portrayal of, 137, 141 Colonization, 1-2, 4., 46, 58-59, 62, 64; benefrrn oi, 16-17, 67-68; Blyden on, 99-107, n6, 130; Chaillec-Bert on, 2.0; definition of, I Comm.unalism (ujamaa), 91, 95 Community: as defined among the B2.ntu, 150; Islamic, II4-15 Conflict (in epistemology), 26-2 7, 8 2, I 90--- 91 Confurmity, 5 2, 5 3 Conquest, ideology of, 69 Consciencism, 1 3 3 Consciencism (Nkrumah), 79, 91, 95 Ccnsci.ousness, 17, 26, 157; African, 36, 77- 78, u:;; black, 77-78, 121; European, 1.0- 21, histcri.cal, 34 Conversations with Ogotemmi!li (Griaule), q.1-43, 178 Conversion, 44-, 4-7-53, 60; Blyden on, u2., I2I Copans, J., 22, 68, 176-77, 178, 179 Coptic church: members in Africa, 5 4 Cosmology, 13-15; in Bantu philosophy, 146, :i:49 Crahay, F., 154, 155-57, 159, 162, 166; Index "'Decollage' conceptud," I 5 5-5 6 Creation: in Bantu philosophy, 139; in Dogon thought, 142 Cri de /'Homme Africain, Le (Ela), 173 Crise du Muntu: Aiithenticite africaine et philosophie, La (Eboussi-Boulaga), 153 Criteriology: in Bantu philosophy, 147, 151 Cn:r.vther, Samuel Aja'/i, 48, 49, 5er-51, 52 Cuius regio, i1lius religio, 4 5 Doguicimi (Hazoume), 77 Donders, J. G., 5 5 Dowayos (people), 2r Drunken King, The (Heusch), 144 DuBois,, \)V. E. B., 90, I 3 I Dum Diversas (Nicholar. V), 4 5 Durkheim, K, 28, 68-69, 82 Dyongu Seru, 14-15 2 35 Cultural anthropology, 184 Eboussi-Boulaga, F., 39-40, 41-42, 60, 157- 58, 167, 169; oa Bantu Philosophy, I4I; Damas, Leou, 83, 90 Christianisme sans fetiche, 173; Crise du Damnes de ia terre, Les (Fanon), 8 5, ':J7- Muntu, I 5 3; criticism of anthropology, Dampierre, E. de, 181-:fa 168; evaluation of Christiani1y, 51-51. Danquah, J.B., 78 Economics, 24-2.6, no; and colonialism, 2.- Darwin, 18 4, Ior-102 Davidson, Basil, 80, 88, 89, 166 Education: Blyden on, 99-Ioo, 102.-103, Dicollage, 156-57, 159 . 120-24 "'Decollage' conceptue!: Conditiocs d'une Edward Wilmot Blyden: Pan-Negro Patriot philosophie bantoue, Le" (Crahay),.I:£5.,J6. . .(Ly:rn;:h),1 30 Deconstruction: of Christianity,. r73.;. i1t .c~n- . Egg 9fthe world, 144 temporary African thought, 164,. 1~5-';67, • E.ii1£U:hlL,1p3g6, , 144-45, 185 De~~~'ss:~t:,5136 ·• Jt;;J~7~3 ~-~l Demonstration: in missionary qiscc;imse;·sr; ,:~1~11gt{,3:9f-t4.0, , 43, H,0-61, I74; study 52-53 .:,:.• ; > ;;..>\,,;f..t,f{\l~bqnche, ~61., 171 Dependency: African tendency tlllWar{1;··1,t;§,).~I1'rRftfcjs_in\r6::,--64,,6 8 D!':s~;~ ~~: ~;"' u2. ,~/ :/{; :: . ;]{~~;~ini sA~fri can education, Derision: in missionary's discoursz,~5;:~§Jt · Descartes, 41 . , ·. ., ;.:,\;;..f · De Servitude, Libertati Christianae CZ.!.J!l.~i gi,'i, < trari~ ('~apitein\ 162 ?~- ~.~~:i·~;;:;,: ; Determ1msm, 3I, 73 ..,.; Development, theology of, 179 ·:.)'.''·~ Dia, Mamadou, 92, 96 Diachrony, 32, 183-89, 193 Diagne, Blaise, 90 Dialectical materialism, 196 Dialectical reason, 34, 86 Dickson~ K., 5 8 Dieterlen, G., I3-I5 Dieu d'eau (Griauie), 67 Diffusionism, 18, 181 .,., . Diodoms of Sicily, 70, 71; quoted,t87 ;;_. ',, Diop, Alioune, 86; ore Bantu Phifosol'i'. 137, q.r, 153 . Diop, Cheikh Anta, 78, 79, 165, 169; .\ . Nations negres et cuiture, 89, 96-:9 1:; :_,;•!l truth of African history, 194-95 · .. ::-.:;. Diop, Majhemout: on Marxism, 96 Discourse on Colonialism (Discours colonia/isme) (Cesaire), 90, 9I, ,53 .. .., . Discourse on Language (Foucault), H, X?4:) Discourse on ths Origin of Inequality Nat~ral History (Buffon), II9 Nduka, 0., 80 Negritude, 38, 83, 86-87, 88, 132-33, 185; in Bantu vision of worid, 79; Blyden as precursor of, 98, 131; in contemporary thought, 166; emphasis on, in Christianity, 53, 60; Horton on, 80; influence on African philosophy, 152, I 5 8; literature of, 36, 83, 85, 86-87; Sartre's role in, 83-87; Senghor on, 92, 93-94; as strategy, 194 Negritude et negroiogues (Adotevi), 167 Negro: Blyden on, III, 114, n8 Negro-Americans. See Black Americans Negro in Ancient History, The (Blyden), 99, 100, 109 Negro personality, 13 I. See also Black personality Neornlor;ialisrn, 176 Neo-Marxism, 166, 168 Index New Testament Backgrnund in cm African Background (.Mbiti), 152 Ngindu, A., 39-40, 43, 162., 171 Ngouabi, M., 91-92 Nicholas V (pope): Dum Diversas, 45 Nietzsche, 4 r, 4 2, 4 3 Nkombe, 0., 80, 173-74 Nkrumah., K., 88, 91, 92, 184; co:npared with Blyden, 9 8, I 3 3; Consciencism, 79, 91, 95; I Speak of Freedom, 95 Noble savage: myths of, uo, !29 Non-Bourgeois The,J/ogy (Danders), 5 5 Norm, 26, 43, 190-91, 192 Nothingness: opposed to being, r~.o Ntedinka, J., 164, 171 Ntu, 147-49 Nusco, L., 202 Nyamuzinda, 148 Nyerere, J., 91, 92, 94-95, 185 Obenga, T., 39-40, 165, 167 Oduyoye, lVL A., 59, 171 Okere, 1:, 39-40, 62, 173-74 O!umide, L. J., 78-79 Ombredane, A., I 66 Ontological hermeneutics, 174 Ontology, 157-58; African philosophy as, rp; in Bantu philosophy, 138-41, 146- 49; in Christian ,heology, 172, I74; in Dagon thought, 14 2. See also Being Oral literature, 181-82 Oral philosophy, 7 5 Oral tradition, 161, 176 Order, principie of, 2.4-2 5, 1. 7 01·igin of Language, The (Rousseau), 72 01igin of Table Manners (Levi-Strauss), 3 5 Ortega y Gasset, Jose, r 88 Other, the, xi, 22, 34.-35, 177, 196; anthropologist as, 3 3; in European consciousness, 20-21; right to be, 6 3; and the Same, 80-82, 96, 180-81; in Senghor's philosophy, 94 Otherness (alterity), 79, 178, 179; 184, 192; in African philosophy, 151, r'p, 157; in -contemporary thought, 162, 166-67, 170, I 7 r; in discourse, 7 2, 8 o-8 I; and history, 190, 195; ideologies for, 86, 87-92; missionaries on, 44, 59; ordering ot in European art, 9, 12; romantic philosophies of, r32 Padmore, G., 96 Paganism, 20, 49--50, 5 8, 63; Blyden on, 121, 124-25, I28 Pagans, 47, 48, 49-50, 112, 121 Pan-African Congresses, 90 Pan-Africanism, 88, 131, 133, 194; Blyden on, 114, 117-18, 130,133 Panafricanism or Communism (Padmore), 96 Index Park, Niungo, 20, I,,o Paroles, I90, I99 Path to Nigerian Freedom (Awolowo), 95 P'Bitek, 0., 140 Peau noire, 1nasques blancs (Fanon), 8 5, 92 Person, Y., I66 Phenomenological method, use of, 174 Philology~ 18, 25-26 Philosophie Bantit comparee, La (Kagame), 145 Philosophie bantu-rwandaise de /'eire, La (Kagame), 57-58, 145 Philosophy: Crahay's defi11ition of, 156 Philosophy, African, ix, 38, 41-43, 74, I52; contempornry aspects of, 15 3-86. See also Bantu philosophy Philosophy, primitive, I3 5-4 5 Philosophy, 'Xlestem, 41-43, 154, 159, 161, I68; compared ·with primitive philosophy, 135-36, 138, 139, 140, 150; methods used in study of African philosophy, 145-47, l~2 Ph"losophy and an African Culture (Wiredu), 161, 163 Pierre Tei/hard de Chardin et /a politique africaine (Senghor), 131 Pigafetta, Filippo, 8 Planet of the Apes (Boulle): quoted, 1, 5-6, 24, 28, 35-3~44,64, 83,145,153 Plant domestication, African, r 3 Pliny, 70-71 Political philosophy, I 6 l Political power, 16, 36, 91,165,170,185 Polytheism, 5 8 Pour la revolution Africaine (fanon), 92 Power, 8, 5 I P-relogism, 72, 82, r 3 6, r 5 5 "T'l:esence Africaine," 86, 157 1 178 Pretres noirs s'interrogent; 56, 176 Primifive Man as a Philosopher (Radin), 154 Primitive (sav-age) mind: Levi-Strauss on, 30- 33; Levy-Bruh! on, 135-36 Primitiveness, 63, 72, 75-76, 82, 108, 191; Blyden on, I rn; as historical invention, I 90; and p21.ganis1n, 20; versus civilization, 197 P!-imitivism: and African philosophy, 15 1 Primitivist strategies, I 9 5 Production: modes of, 196-97; processes of, 4, 170; relations of, 60, 170~ r89j 196 Prophetism, n6, 173 Pmpos d'tme theologie africaine, Le (Tshibangu), 171 Protestant churches, 19, 45, 49, 54, 55, 127 Psychology, 26, 73, 1<9-50, 166 Quakers: in Ke117a, 5 5 Race: Blyden on, no, n4, u5-16, n7, 118-20, I:17, r29-30, 131-32; European vie·ws of, 107, 108 Racism, 8 5; in Blyden's theories, 104-ro5, 106, H9, 129-30 Radin, E, 1 54 Reason, 51, 136 Recherches philosophiques Africaines, I 60 Reci.t pour soi: propounded by Eboussi- Boulaga, 42, 169 Reduction, p, 66, 68 Reformation, the, 4 5 Refutation, 51, 52-53 Relatione del Reame di Congo (Pigafetrn), 8 Relativism, 86, 131, 171; in Blyden's theories, n3-14, 133; in Levi-Strauss's thought, 33 Religion: Blyden on, 120, 124-28. See also Christianity; Islam; Religions, African Religions, African, 56, 58, 59-6,, 63, 76, 88; Blyden on, 124-2 5; and Christian theology, 171; ethnocentric theories on, 73- 74 Rembrandt: depiction of blacks, 9 Renascent Africa (Azikiwe), 90 Revelation, 58, 141, 173 Ricoeur, Paul, 19-21, 34, 57, 183-84, 195 Rigaud, Hyacinthe: depiction of blacks, 9 Ripa, Cesare: African Allegory, 12 Ritual, 14-15, 144 Roman Catholicism, 39-40, 137, 162; Blyden on, 126-27; members in Africa, 54-55; missionaries, 45-46, 48; perspective on traditional religions, 58-59, 61-62 Romano, E Giovanni, 48-49, 50-51, 52, 53 Roman writers: on Africa, 69-71; on blacks, IIO, I20 Rossini, Carlo Conti, 202 Rousseau~ I 5 7 2, I I 9 Rubens, Peter Paul: depiction of blacks, 9 Ru!e, 26, 43, 190-91, 192, 193 Sachs, I.,~ Sagala: in Dogon cosmology, I3-14,, r 5 Sagan, Carl: on Dogon astronomy, 13-15 Salkin, P., 76 Salvation, theology of, 52--54, 66 Sarne, Ihe, 20, 22, 177, 198; history of, 28, 33, 34-35, 177, 180; identity of, in European art, v,; and the Oi:her, 80-82, 96, 180-81, 199; and v:oience, 43, 196 Sameness, 72, 83 Sartre, J.-P., 83-87, 90-91; Biach Orpheus, 83-85, 90-91, 92, 132; Levi-Strauss on, 34, 35 Saul, John, ,97-98 Saussure, F. de, 190 Savage (primitive) mind: Levi-Strauss on, 30- 3 3; Levy-Bmhl on, r 3 5-3 6 Savages, :10, 42, 47, 75, 103; Crowther on, 49; Enlightenment views on, 17, 72; explorers' discourse on, I 3 ~ I 6 Scheub, H., 182 Schmidt, VI., 58, 176, 185, 194; concept of UrmonotheisnzusJ 76, 81; Urspvung der Gottesidee, 76 Scholastic grids: used in analysis of Bantu philosophy, 146-50 Schuchardt, H., I 8 Schulter, Andreas: Africa, 12 Schum peter, J. A., 2-3 Science, 16, 65, 123, 165; relationship to niagic, 3 0-3 I; role in modernization, 169- 70, 1 74-75 Science of the abstract~ 30, 3r-32 Science of the concrete, 30, 31-32 Sculpture, African, II Second Order, 163-64, 171 Selected Letters of Edward Wilmot Blyden (Lynch, ed.), 98 Self: recit pour soi as way to, 42; relationship· to the Other, 181 Semiology, 183 Senghor, L. S., 43, 86, 184-85; on Blyden, 98-99, 131; compared with Blyden, 123, I 3 2; and negritude, 8 3-84, 8 5, 8 8, 9 2, 9 3- 94 Shorter, A., 73-7 4 Signification, 26-27, 37, 41, 82, 190-91, 193, 195 Sigui ritual: and Dogon cosmology, 14-15 Silent philosophy, I 52. Sirius and Sirius B, 13-15 Slavery, 9, 58-59, rn8, 169; Blyden on, rno, 103, 105, 119, 132; under Islam, 1q.-15 Slave trade, ro, 100, 114-15, 119 Smet, A. J., 74, 136, q.r, 160-61 Snowden, E M., 69 Social and human sciences, 17-18, 37, 61, 79, 176, 179-80; contemporary African philosophy on, 164, 165-70, 174-75; Foucault on, :;,,,62~ 7; Levi-Strauss on, 28; pluralization of, 192 Social Anthropology and Other Essays (Evans-Pritchard), 67-68 Social classes: gap between, I 8 5 Socialism, 91-92, 93-9 5 Sociology, 73, 166, 176, 173, 179-80, 184 Soldier: role of, 46-47 Sodipo, J. 0., 39-40, 161 Sm;v, I. E. B., 18, 39-40 Spencer, 189-90 Springer, Bartolomaus, 6-7 Strain theory: l3lyden's ideology as, 131-32 Structuralism, 19, 35, 177-78, 179-80, 187, 198-99 Sumner, C.: editions of Ethiopian treatises, 163, 201-203 Sur la philosophie africaine (Hountondji), 158 Surnaturel et la Nature dans la mentalite primitive, Le (Levy-Bruh!), 13 5 Synchrony, 32, 177-78, 189, 194 Syncretic churches, 5 4 System, 26, 43, 190-91 Index Taboo-laws: in the Bantu community, 150 Taylor, J. V., 54 Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre, 94 Tempe!s, Placide Frans, 48, 50-54, 136-41., 177-78, 179; Bantu Philosophy, 50, 67, 136-42, 144; on colonization, 67-68; contemporary philosophers on, 153-56, 157- 58) 159; I(agame on, 1:45-46 Temu, A., 197 Terrn nullius, 4 5, 46 Theodicy: in Bantu philosophy, 146, 149 Theology: contemporaiy African views, 59- 63, 170-74, 178-79; epistemolvgical debate on, 164-65 Theories of Primitive Religion (Evans-Pritchard), 73 Theuws, J. A., 182 Thornton, R., 15-16 Tidy, M., 169 Tiv mythology, 14 3 Toure, Ahmed Sekou, 91, 91. Tourist art, 11-12 Towa, M., 39-40, 43,157,158,160,165 Towards Nationhood in West Africa (Graft- Johnson), 90 Toward the Decolonizatio11 of A/rican Literature (Chinweizu, Jemie and Mudobuike), 168-69 Tradition, 4, 76-77, 169, 189, 191-92; role in ethnophilosophy, I 5 3; versus modernity, 197, 198 Traite de metaphysique (Vo!taire), II9 Transhistoric thought, 187, 188-89, 198 Travelers' reports, 69-72, I 8 9 Treatise of Ziir'y Yacob and of Walda Heywat, The (Sumner, ed.), 163, 201-202, 203 Tristes Tropiques (Levi-Strauss), 33, 35 Truth, 41, 47, 51, 165; will to, 15, 27, 41, 63 Tshiamalenga, N., u,o, 149, 160-61, 173- 74, I83 Tshibangu, T., 164, 171-72 Turgot, A. R. J ., 6 Ugirashebuja, 0., 43, 162, 171 Ujamaa (communalism), 91, 95 Unconscious, 34, 3 5, 3 7-3 8 Universal civilization: Senghor on, 94 Universalism: in Kagame's philosophy, 151 Untu, 79 Urmonotheism11s, 76, 8 r Urspnmg der Afrikcnischen Kulturen (Frobenius), n-2.3 U:-sprung der Gottesidee, Die (Schmidt), 76 Van der Kerken, G., 74 Vanneste, A., 164 Van Overbergh, C., 7 4 Van Pa1ys, J.M., 163, 202 Vansina, J., 39, 80-81, 166, 176, 194 Index Varenius, 10, 191 Vatic:m Council, first: on curse of Ham, 46 Vaughan, A. T., 129-30 Velasquez, Diego: depiction of blacks, 6, 9 Verhaegen, B., 167, 178-79 Veyne, Paul, 17-18, 23, 83, 180, 198; on history, 192-93, 196, 198 Vindication of the .Negro Race, A (Blyden), 99, 108 Vital force. See Force Voltaire, TL, n9 Von Daniken, E., r 5 'Wagner, R., 27, 67, 184 Wake:fieldjE . Go~I OI Wealth, theory of, 2.4-25 Weber, M., 17-18, 192 Weltanschauungen, xi, 33, 74, 75,135,175; and .African philosophy, 15 4; of the Bantu, 149, 15 5-56; described by anthropologists, I 5 2 Western Sciences: What For? (Buakasa), 174 West Indian Blacks: Blyden on, 105, n7, 130 \1Vhite, H., 3 3 Williams, G., 16-17, 46 Will to truth, 15, 27, 41, 63 Wiredu, K., 39-40, 161-62, 163, 168 °\Jlfomen: new African theology on, 179 Yai, 0., 160 Zoungrana, Paul Cardinal, 6
+++

Copyleft, CC, Mitzub'ixi Quq Chi'j, 1996-2099